The daemon’s fate is produced by a
necessity that can only be described as an indeterminate or unknowable
cause. In this way, Empedocles gives a name to that which is unknowable
and incalculable. There is, moreover, no sense in which the daemon’s
banishment can be accounted for in terms of the Christian psychology of
sin. The daemon has not sinned in the modern psychological sense of
freely and consciously choosing a particular course of action. Rather, as
M. R. Wright puts it, “although the daimon has come under the power of
Strife . . . this need not imply wrong intention or power of choice on the
part of the daimon.”17 For Empedocles, and for other pre-Socratics like
Heraclitus, character was an objective and not a subjective phenomenon.
As is seen in the example of Empedocles’ daemon, one’s character is not
really a matter of choice or subjective will; rather, human acts are seen to
flow from an external, divine agency associated with necessity.18
Accordingly, when Heraclitus states in fragment 119 that “a person’s
character is his daemon,” the term daemon may mean either one’s fate or
one’s guardian divinity.19 In his commentary on fragment 119, T. M.
Robinson argues that the fragment may in fact carry both meanings.
Hence, on the one hand, a daemon may be the soul of a noble individual
who has died — a soul that will subsequently function as a guardian
divinity that protects another person during his or her life, thereby influencing
his or her fate. On the other hand, however, the fragment may
also mean that the person’s own character, and not the soul of another
individual who has died, is their daemon. In this latter sense, according to
Robinson, “one’s own character is also one’s destiny (daemon)” and in
this sense one is completely responsible “for the daemon that is one’s
character.”20 This notion of responsibility is, however, definitely not to be
equated with modern notions concerning the consequences that arise
from the actions of free and autonomous agents. As Charles H. Kahn
observes, Heraclitus identified the individual character with the elemental
powers and constituents of the cosmos. It is these elemental powers, as
opposed to the individual’s freedom and autonomy, that “constitute the
physical explanation or psychophysical identity of the particular life in
question, the elemental equivalent of a given moral and intellectual
character.”21
Similarly, the catastrophic split between the forms and the physical
world depicted by Plato in Timaeus should not be confused with the
Christian Fall. Although, as Ronna Burger points out, the Platonic split
does have something in common with original sin, in the sense that all
humans are born fallen and “in ignorance of the truth,” the split cannot
be said to have occurred as the result of sin in the Christian sense. Rather,
it occurs simply because it was not possible to bring beings based upon
the forms into existence without making them temporal and corporeal.22
The temporal world is fallen, but not in any moral or psychological way:
rather, its fallen-ness is its necessity, as the act of creation in Plato is necessarily
an act of division.
With regard to the fates of individuals, the Platonic daemon is likewise
connected with the notion of necessity, although the idea of sin re-
ceives a stronger treatment in Plato than it does in Empedocles. In the
“Myth of Er” section of The Republic (614b–621d) Plato, through the
character of Er, gives an account of the transmigration of souls similar to
that found in Empedocles’ “Decree of Necessity.” Er, having died in
battle, encounters the “other world” in which souls are allotted their
fates, and then returns to life to tell of his experiences. Er has been
appointed by the judges of the other world as a messenger charged with
reporting to earthly men the events that take place there. He refers to
this other world as a topos daimonios (daemonic place, 614c) as it is here
that souls are required to choose their fates or lots for the next life. The
lots are distributed by Lachesis, the daughter of necessity, and they include
both animal and human forms of life. Each soul may choose its
respective lot, but this choice is soon forgotten, as the souls proceed to
the forgetful river at Lethe and, after drinking their fill, they forget all of
their experiences in the daemonic world, subsequently returning to life
ignorant of their choice of lot. Thus, although Plato implies that each
soul chooses its lot and is therefore responsible for this choice, in the trajectory
of life itself the choice of lots is forgotten, and life appears to be
governed by necessity.
What does Plato mean by calling this other world a daemonic place?
Here daemonic can mean both “of necessity” and “of divination” or
“mantic.” In Heraclitus’s sense of the daemon as the nexus between character
and fate, the world experienced by Er is one in which souls are once
more fated (that is, given a lot) for their next incarnation. This interpretation
also accords with the etymological origin of daemonic in the word
daio, which refers to the division and distribution of divine gifts by the
gods.23 Er’s role as an intermediary or courier who brings news of the
hidden world is also daemonic in the mantic or divinatory sense. The experiences
that he reports take place in an intermediate, transitional world
suspended between life and death, and he himself is something like the
living dead, having mysteriously arisen from his own funeral pyre. Overwhelmingly,
however, the “Myth of Er” is a testament to the inexorable
and unfathomable workings of necessity. This is seen when Plato gives us
a detailed rendering, at 616b–c, of the “Spindle of Necessity” that revolves
upon a “straight light like a pillar . . . extended from above
throughout the heaven and the earth” (PCD, 840), demonstrating the
extent to which Plato’s version of the daemonic is literally a kind of
conduit or tube that transports divine or numinous information to the
physical realm.