Is utilitarianism an acceptable ethic for animals?
Before this question can be answered it will be important to define a few things. What do we mean by utilitarianism and what does it mean to say it is, or isn’t an acceptable ethic for animals ? On what criteria is ‘acceptable’ being judged? I shall leave the former definition for the opening part of this essay and deal now with the latter. I shall understand the phrase “an acceptable ethic for animals†as an ethic which can realistically be applied to animals and one which is practical when applied to the real world. These are the criteria by which I shall judge the success or failure of utilitarianism. Utilitarianism, as an all-encompassing ethical theory has many proponents and opponents but this essay will only deal with its application to animals and the arguments surrounding it.
In this essay I will first describe the type of utilitarianism which is to be defended, namely preference utilitarianism as supported by animal rights philosopher and activist, Peter Singer. Where there is a significant differing implication between the preference type and other forms of utilitarianism, I shall make note of it. The remainder of the essay will focus on the objections to the utilitarian view, both those that believe it goes too far in defending animals and those, such as Tom Regan, who believe it does not go far enough. An analysis of the theory itself and its criticisms will enable us to conclude whether or not it is an acceptable ethic for animals.
Preference utilitarianism
Preference utilitarianism is a particular type of utilitarianism which defines the good to be maximized as the fulfilment of persons’ preferences. Like any utilitarian theory, preference utilitarianism claims that the right thing to do is that which produces the best consequences; when defined in terms of preference satisfaction, the best consequences can include things other than pure hedonism, like reputation or rationality. So how does this apply to animals? The contractarian view of morality is that only those who have the capacity to enter into a contract can enter into the moral sphere. Since animals do not have this capacity they cannot be considered moral beings. As such, the only morally relevant issues surrounding animals are ones which indirectly affect humans or the animals as property. Singer rejects this view citing the principle of equal consideration of interests.
If a being suffers there can be no moral justification for refusing to take that suffering into consideration (Singer 1975). In his Animal Liberation, Singer quotes Jeremy Bentham, one of the founders of the utilitarian school of thought, who says, ‘The question is not, Can they reason? nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?’
The morally significant attribute that all animals, including humans, share is they have the capacity for suffering and enjoyment or happiness. It is just as arbitrary (and in fact what Singer calls speciesist) to draw the line of equality between different species as it is between different races and sexes or between those with differing intelligence or cognitive capacities. What’s more, Bentham also says “Each to count for one and none for more than one†which includes animals as well as humans.
Singer sums it up saying that ‘the essence of the principle of equal consideration of interests is that we give equal weight in our moral deliberations to the like interests of all those affected by our actions’. Since animals have preferences and can be affected by our actions, those preferences must be given equal weight to that of humans on an individual basis. In this way, preference utilitarianism is an acceptable ethic for animals because, by virtue of the principle of equality of consideration, it, unlike contractarian ethics, can be applied to them.
Preference utilitarianism in practice
There are three main areas in which preference utilitarianism has practical implications on animal welfare; the meat industry, animal experimentation and animal sports. In ‘Animal Liberation’ Singer dedicates a chapter on the first two and in other publications, talks about the third. In each case he gives examples of the status quo and the considerable amount of suffering that animals go through, unnecessarily, all over the world. Using preference utilitarianism, he describes what he believes should change in each case. With regards to the meat industry, he argues that we should all become vegetarians since the pleasure we may get from eating meat does not justify the suffering that animals go through in factory farms. He says that the majority of animal experimentation should stop since in most cases it does not directly save human life and therefore cannot be considered worthwhile. And finally, he says that the enjoyment that people may get out of taking part in hunts or watching bullfights, does not outweigh the suffering of the animals. These are all simplified but the point is to show that preference utilitarianism has real and significant practical implications for our society and the way we treat animals. As such, this is evidence that the theory can be put into practice with real results which minimise the suffering of animals.
Is it an acceptable ethic for animals?
So we’ve seen that utilitarianism and specifically preference utilitarianism can in theory be applied to animals, but does it go far enough? Proponents of animal rights, such as Tom Regan, don’t believe it does. Regan claims that animals, as what he calls ‘subjects-of-a-life’, are bearers of rights like humans, although not necessarily of the same degree. This means that animals in this class have “inherent value” as individuals, and cannot merely be considered as the means to an end. (Regan 1985) This is different to the utilitarian view which does not consider animals as having inherent moral value over and above its capacity to suffer or be happy. So where is the tension?
Consider an example where performing fatal experiments on 10 rats, which would cause them extreme pain and suffering, could save the life of a human. The utilitarian would weigh up the expected outcomes and most likely decide that it was right for the experiments to go ahead. The rights theorist like Regan, who adopts a strict Kantian idea that animals should never be used as a means to an end, by contrast would say that experimentation on animals was always wrong. The utilitarian ethic, according to Regan, does not go far enough in protecting animals and as such is not an acceptable ethic to apply. I do not accept this criticism since I would agree with Singer and the utilitarians that human life is of greater worth than animal life due to our ability to be self-ware, capable of abstract thought, of planning for the future etc. As such, I would accept that there could be a justification for animal experimentation if there was no other alternative, the suffering of the animals being experimented on was minimised and the saving of a human life was guaranteed. All of these restrictions are compatible with a utilitarian perspective and take into consideration the welfare of animals.
One of the criticisms of people who believe that animals have rights is that rights can only be given to beings that can make moral judgements. Carl Cohen, writing in a medical journal said:
“The holders of rights must have the capacity to comprehend rules of duty governing all, including themselves. In applying such rules, the holders of rights must recognize possible conflicts between what is in their own interest and what is just. Only in a community of beings capable of self-restricting moral judgments can the concept of a right be correctly invoked." (Cohen, 1986)
Clearly animals do not have this capacity and therefore cannot have rights. This is a criticism that proponents of animal rights such as Tom Regan have to deal with. However, preference utilitarianism dodges this criticism because it does not claim that animals have rights but that we should given consideration to animal welfare. It puts more emphasis on our duty towards animals rather than affirming rights for animals themselves. This makes preference utilitarianism a more widely acceptable ethic than ones which demand animal rights.
Is there anything about the ethic of utilitarianism that would make in unacceptable when applied to animals? One concern is that of demandingness. The ethic requires us to minimize the suffering of animals whenever possible. At present, billions of animals suffer every year due to the factory farm industry, animal experimentation and animal sports. On top of that animals are suffering due to environmental issues e.g. 99% mortality rate in sewer rats due to lack of food. This would suggest there is an international emergency in terms of animal welfare. As a result, minimising the suffering of such a large amount of animals seems extremely demanding and in some cases impractical. Devoting our resources to minimising animal suffering could have undesirable consequences in other areas of life. However, I do not accept this as an argument against preference utilitarianism as an ethic. It is not an ethic which requires a binary state. Any amount of minimising suffering is better than none and although the process may be gradual, it can be conceived as a ladder to climb.
Another objection to utilitarianism, one which is broader than the issues of animal welfare, is that it’s sometimes impossible to know what will maximise happiness in the long run. As a consequentialist ethical theory, utilitarianism relies on expected outcomes of a situation. The outcome that maximises happiness and minimises suffering in the short terms is often relatively easy. However, is it possible that what we think is the best outcome now, may not be the best in the long run? In his essay ‘Why I am only a Demi-Vegetarian’, Richard Hare (perhaps unknowingly) provides us with an example of this. Preference utilitarians such as Singer argue that we should all become vegetarians and stop eating meat because by not buying meat, the meat industry will eventually collapse as an economic inevitability. However, Hare argues that this not necessarily the correct outcome. (Hare 1993)
Suppose that a large proportion of people became vegetarians and stopped buying meat. The meat industry as a whole would be forced to cut its prices and as a result only the most efficient producers would be able to stay in the market. Usually, the most efficient producers, i.e. the ones which can charge the least for its produce, are the least ethical. Factory farms which can produce much larger amounts of meat in a shorter amount of time will often keep animals in very small cages to maximise space, causing them a lot of suffering. More ethical farmers, who allow their animals to have free-reign and are raised and killed ethically, will be forced out of the market because their produce will almost always be more expensive. The answer then says Hare, is to become what he calls a demi-vegetarian; someone who eats mostly vegetables but supplements their diet with a bit of meat which is ethically sourced. By doing so, the demi-vegetarian is able to buy meat produced by the ethical farmers, thus keeping them in business, while also causing the meat industry as a whole to become much less intensive. This is clearly an example of how utilitarianism can provide ‘right’ answers in the short term which end up causing more suffering in the long term. Perhaps what is even more damning is that although Hare is a self-style Kantian utilitarian, his views are very similar to Singer and yet they still come to different conclusions.
So what is the conclusion? It seems true to say that preference utilitarianism, based on the principle of equal consideration of interest, provides a possible ethic for animals inasmuch that it is not nonsensical to consider animals as morally relevant due to the fact that drawing the moral line at the species level seems arbitrary. The utilitarian view seeks to provide for the welfare of animals and minimise suffering but manages to dodge the objections raised against animal rights theorists by not claiming that animals have rights. This renders it more acceptable as an ethical theory. There is no doubt that when applied, utilitarianism does indeed provide better welfare for animals and that the outcome of better welfare for animals is an ethic which can be universally applied. However, there is a worry that it is not always possible to tell what is the best action to take in order to achieve that outcome. The issue of animal welfare is connected not only with the moral issues that surround it, but also with the economic and environmental spheres which could be impacted by a utilitarian ethic. In essence I think it is fair to say that utilitarianism is an acceptable ethic for animals. The main difficulty, facing the whole spectrum of animal rights activists, is getting people to agree and act on it.
Bibliography
HARE, R. M. Why I am only a Demi-Vegetarian in Essays on Bioethics, Clarendon Press, Oxford 1993.
REGAN, T. The Case for Animal Rights, University of California Press, California 1985.
SINGER, P. Animal Liberation, Thorsons Publishers Limited, Wellingborough, Northamptonshire 1975.
SINGER, P. Practical Ethics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1979.