Justified True Belief and Critical Rationalism.

“Justified True Belief and Critical Rationalism.”

During his trial Socrates argued that human wisdom came from the acknowledgement of human ignorance (Plato, 1969, P. 52), a position arrived at via the traditional account of knowledge as justified true belief. Because of such conclusions this account, which leaves us without a useful “knowledge”, is not without its detractors. Therefore the traditional theory of knowledge as justified true belief will be outlined. Its success, strengths and weakness as an account of knowledge will be assessed in relation to competing theories such as “critical rationalism”, where knowledge is not infallible but merely the best available theory (Popper, 1984, p. 26-7).

The question of demarcation between belief and knowledge has been a central debate in epistemology. The traditional account of knowledge considered belief to be an essential component of knowledge. For the purpose of argument, the proposition “time is a dimension in relation to other dimensions” is true. But if the individual does not believe it to be so then they don’t know it. This is the first condition of the traditional theory of knowledge, the belief condition. A belief may be true or false, but knowledge must be true. The second condition of knowledge is the Truth condition.

A proposition that meets the first two conditions of the traditional epistemological theory is not necessarily considered knowledge, as it still has to satisfy the evidence condition. According to this position, a propositions status as knowledge is not based on belief or accidental truth, but must be justified to the point of infallibility in order to be considered knowledge.

The infallibility of knowledge has been a controversial point for epistemologists. The truth condition, according to the traditional theory has to be satisfied in order for a proposition to be considered knowledge. But the truth or falsity of a proposition is determined by the justification. A proposition can be considered true and justified on the basis of all available evidence, but a contrary observation can disprove a long held piece of knowledge, this is the “problem of induction” (Popper, 1984, p. 42). This is not the only problem with the evidence condition. The infinite regress of reasons that one proposition is justified with another, is a problem for the traditional account of knowledge. If one proposition is supported by another and so forth until there is a whole system of propositions, it becomes self-referring without finding a foundation which justifies the totality of propositions.

Foundational and fallibility issues have been central weakness of the traditional account of knowledge. There have been varied attempts to solve the problem of knowledge, either in proposing foundations in an attempt to solve the infinite regress of reasons, or by weakening the idea of infallibility of knowledge. Theses philosophers opt to define knowledge as the best available theory on the basis of all current evidence to avoid scepticism, the position that we have no knowledge.

Epistemological foundationalism, in both its empiricist and rationalist variants has attempted to ground knowledge and thus save the justified true belief account of knowledge from both the infinite regress of reasons and scepticism. These problems left unsolved would invalidate any synthetic propositions claim to knowledge. Empiricist conceived that all knowledge was grounded in the senses. John Locke expressed the idea in his phrase “Tabula Rasa” that the human mind is like a blank canvas getting filled in by experience (Teichman, Evens, 1991 p.246). This foundational theory, which does not weaken the evidence condition, is still subject to the infinite regress of reasons, the problem of induction, the fallibility of sense-observations and thus all the problems associated with the traditional account of knowledge.

Perceptual information can lead to false propositions; Descartes recognising this fact chose to doubt his ability to know the external world (Descartes, 1984, p.96). Retaining the evidence condition as proposed by the traditional account of knowledge Descartes looked for foundational propositions which are self-evident and therefore indubitable. Synthetic propositions which are contingent upon empirical verification are fallible, but analytical propositions which are true by necessity of meaning are candidates for epistemological foundations. The distinction between analytical and synthetic propositions can be illustrated with two examples of the different types of propositions. The proposition “all triangles have three sides”, is an analytical proposition. Its truth-value is not determined by empirical evidence but by the meaning of the word triangle, a shape with three sides. Synthetic propositions make claims about the world; “all rabbits are white” is an example. Its truth-value is contingent upon the state of the world, whether or not all rabbits are white. Descartes in his argument from dreaming held that true analytical propositions are knowledge by the standard of justified true belief (Descartes, 1984, p. 98). The usefulness of analytical propositions, and hence knowledge found within the paradigm of the traditional account is considered a major of weakness of the theory.

Competing theories of epistemology have contested the conditions under which knowledge is traditionally defined. The critical rationalism of Karl Popper has contested the infallibility clause in the evidence condition and thus paradoxically the truth condition of knowledge. The truth-value of a proposition is therefore not the determining factor of its value as knowledge but rather its truth-argument being able to account for all available evidence better than all other propositions. For Popper knowledge was not static, but a developing project, “the advance of knowledge consists, mainly, in the modification of earlier knowledge” (Popper, 1984, p. 28). Accordingly by this theory the replacement of one set of ideas by another that constituted a better explanation of all available evidence, is not an occasion to morn our inability to gain knowledge, but rather a moment of increasing knowledge. This theory also provides a demarcation between knowledge and belief, which preferences knowledge over belief in a workable manner. If according to the traditional account, knowledge was infallible it would not be useful because only analytical propositions can meet such criteria. Belief then would be more useful then knowledge, invalidating any attempt by traditional account epistemologists to give us practical reasons to preference knowledge over belief

For the critical rationalist knowledge is a process of development based around a method of trial and error (Popper, 1984, p. 56). Therefore along with the truth and evidence condition, the belief condition is challenged. Because we do not have to believe our current theories to be true, they might be true, while falsified theories are believed to be untrue (Popper, 1984, p.56). The weakness of this theory is that it overturns all the three conditions which make knowledge definite and solid. It finds strength in circumventing the problems (infinite regress of reasons, foundations and infallibility issues) associated with the traditional account of knowledge. Hence synthetic propositions, both useful and informative are considered knowledge according to critical rationalism. This constitutes a functional rather than dysfunctional system of knowledge, because it makes allowances for adaptability which the traditional account does not.

The traditional account of knowledge as justified true belief, aims to make knowledge a concrete concept, giving us a clear cut method for discerning between what we know and don’t know. But the conclusion of this method leads to a situation where knowledge is either non-existent (scepticism) or useless (rationalist) Socrates himself concluded the former (Plato, 1969, P. 52). The critical rationalists and best available theory epistemologists allow for a working concept of knowledge by weakening the criterion for something to be known. The traditional theory of knowledge is ultimately unsuccessful because while it considers knowledge more justified then belief, it gives no practical reason to preference knowledge over forms of information such as a mere belief, which while not being certainly true can be informative and useful. Hence the traditional account does not provide a functional theory of knowledge.

Bibliography

Descartes, R. (1984), Discourse on Method and The Meditations, Penguin, Bungay.

Plato, (1969), The Last Days of Socrates, Trans Tredennick, H. Penguin, London.

Popper, K. R. (1984), Conjectures and Refutations, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.

Teichman, J. Evans, K. C. (1991), Philosophy a beginner’s guide, Basil Blackwell, Cambridge.

very nice paper…

are you familiar with the gettier problem?

en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gettier_problem

-Imp

i’ve heard of, but not read into the Gettier problem. Epistemology isnt a big interest for me, i’m just trying to get through a class. loll, i got 14 and a half out of 15 for this papper.

I submitted another one under the title of something like (if I remember correctly) “The Logic of Existential Meaning” - are you going to publish that or is it too rife with spelling and grammatical errors?

Down with Syntax, it’s a Grand-narrative that oppresses the other, who is not metaphysial present in the syntactically gifted categorization of binary oppositions. (put a couple of Lacan and derrida references in there and we’re cool?)

Wonderful and truly enjoyable.

Now, I don’t know how much this might help but the absurd conclusions of philosophies always have me revisit the propositions, the truth of which one can question, again and again. For example, according to “the traditional theory”, the truth condition “has to be satisfied in order for a proposition to be considered knowledge.”
From such a genesis, is it really surprising that we end in absurdity? Isn’t such justifications, outside of a philosopher’s chair, mere rationalizations; excuses after the act of faith/belief?
I am right now drinking my cappuccino. This is a fact for me. Now, the logician might question how do I know that I am drinking a cappuccino and not some beverage that tastes like it. Pressed in this way, I might surrender my “knowledge” and hide in ignorance, which is what most sceptics have done, or come up with a defense of my belief. Justifications. But to me, the act of drinking represents the justification.
The cappo might be filled with preservatives or some other stuff, all artificial and bearing no resemblance to the original-- in fact this can be said of most american pizzas-- but if it looks like a cappuccino, tastes like a cappuccino etc, etc, etc, then that is to be consumed by me as a cappo. Whatever other differences it might have with a sacred Sicilian cappo, these differences must be discovered and then, only qualify what is similar to a cappo. If you will, it would be a “artificially flavored cappo”. The two substances, however are “synonymous”, physically speaking, because I cannot tell the difference, unless i study the ingredients.

The truth or falsity of my cappo is not then determined by justifications I provide my interrogator, but by whether or not it makes a difference to me. Is the difference a matter of degree or one of kind? remember that cat/rabbit scenario? Well, to me the excersice proves little because, geometrically, a cat and a rabbit are similar. And as far as language some words do represent both. Back to my cappo. Suppose, due to some act of God, I ask for a cappo and when I start to drink it it tastes, to me at least, like lemonade. Will I still call my drink a cappo? Further, my reaction is to ask:“What the fuck?! I ordered a cappo, and you gave me a lemonade!!” Will it matter to me that a young punk by the machine assures me that the ingredients he used did not contain a single lemon? And if proven that the laws of physics do not exist and that indeed it was the case that, in this particular case, as hard as it is to believe, coffe grounds, water and milk came to taste like lemons, would I now call this a cappo? No, and a thousand times No. “Why?” Because the truth and falsity of my cappo is not contingent on arguments, justifications and words, but my reaction to the beverage; by my taste buds.

We believe a lot of things, but “believing” need not be a matter of reason. Nature has given me lungs that would be useless underwater. In this sense…in a sense…the human body infers that an oxigen-filled athmosphere is. Now, where is it’s justification?

The Infinite regress you speak in your paper of (“The infinite regress of reasons that one proposition is justified with another, is a problem for the traditional account of knowledge. If one proposition is supported by another and so forth until there is a whole system of propositions, it becomes self-referring without finding a foundation which justifies the totality of propositions.”) is defeated, in my mind, by it’s inability to account for the subjective- that is, my taste buds. Not every proposition needs a justification. As much fun as that can be, one can also ask if there is a reason to doubt a held belief. This is not a popular view, but it seems valid to me, for without such a view, miracles should be as believable as any other occurrence. Thus, I would maintain that I am immortal until further notice, or death. The foundation of a belief is our reaction to it. These reactions are not justified logically-- I cannot convince a logician why I may put sunscreen in Puerto Rico, or why I avoid fire from a certain distance. What I can be said to “know” or “not know” of Fire, depends on what I do or don’t do in the face of it. It is this and not some endless discourses of justifications, which remain always a subjective matter, or the satisfaction of a need for a basis, or foundation that finally settles, at least for me, the idea of what we can conceive as “known”.
I can of course doubt this or that, but every doubt arises from another plea for certainty, or knowledge of some kind. I could doubt that “all men are mortal”, but only if I would “know” of a comfirmed instance of this not being the case or the conditions under which some men would be immortal. If I doubt the value of science fiction as well, then I have no basis for doubting the former belief that all men must die.

In the end I like Popper’s ideas too, and see “knowledge” as a journey and not a place. Yet, it is a journey we take in these mini-ships we call our “bodies”. The questions asked and the answers found, or considered, are collected and cataloged by the sensors and computer we possess at this time-- limited by the technology we have managed to accomplish so far. We live by them, because, although I may use the metaphor of a ship, in reality, our bodies are different in that we are the ship. There is no duality. We’re the sensor and the computer and the technology is not of our creation but of our evolution and enviroment. Why do we believe, then, in our senses-- even when wrong, consciously or not-- and our inferences (computer)? Because we are them and by them.