phoneutria wrote:Silhouette wrote:Eating half an apple, then half of that and half of that, which I believe is what you're saying, leaves partial products of slightly more than nothing at all and the limit of the process approaches zero apple.
approaches half apple
For the life of me I can't make sense of this from your wording as approaching half an apple... must be my fault, right? Demonstration please?
\(\prod_{k=0}^\infty(\frac1{2})^k=0\)
Type "infinite product of (1/2)^k" into Wolfram Alpha.
It's the same for any fraction less than 1 (starting with 1 whole apple and proceding to eat any possible fraction of it) and for any k value as a starting point... - you always get zero.
Eat half of a whole apple, you have half left
Eat half of the remaining half, you have a quarter left
Eat half of the remaining quarter, you have an eighth left
Etc. down to the limit of nothingness...
phoneutria wrote:it's not an original thought
all of scientific research operates with this in mind
utility is a compromise
The scientific method is indeed a process of relative improvement, rather than a sure way to arrive at absolute truth - but like dialectics, even with the realisation of compromise, it's intended to
tend towards truth or at least a more truthful representation of reality.
Utility being at odds with truth realises that all knowledge, even that refined by the scientific method is in fact a tendency
away from the truth of continuity.
Ecmandu wrote:Yeah! I get to play devils advocate to Magnus for a moment!
Magnus writes a number like:
2,4,6, 1... (1 repeating)
Now!
1,1,1,1.... (repeating) is possibly 8 smaller in VALUE, but not correspondence!
For example:
3.000...
Is smaller in VALUE than PI.
Correspondence however is the same.
I don't think Magnus meant that by his ellipsis, but I agree with you that 1 repeating would amount to infinity all the same.
If the 2 corresponds with the first 1, the 4 with the second, the 6 with the third, and with all 1s matching after that, the total difference would be 1+3+5=9, not 8. Is that what you meant by the difference in value? Either way any apparent "value difference" from looking at only the start would get swallowed up by the undefined essence of finitude-being-opposed (infinity). The superficial appearance of different finite values at the start does nothing.
I assume by representing \(3\) as \(3.\dot0\) and corresponding each decimal place with \(\pi\), you get bijection and therefore the implication that the quantities are the same size - or at least the cardinality of the sets is the same.
If it can be accepted that adding in the appropriate number of 0s to any set, and that you can therefore theoretically induce bijection for everything and anything, this would throw into question the whole notion of set cardinality being evaluated by bijection.
It's a big "if" though, but I'm struggling to see any flaws in it other than what I said about quantities that require the quality of infinity to denote them correctly, and those that don't require it (e.g. recurring 0s either before or after any stated finites).
Magnus Anderson wrote:\(0 \times 0 \times 0 \times \cdots\) is an infinite product. It's a product made out of an infinite number of terms. It has no end.
Agree?
Even though \(0 \times 0 \times 0 \times \cdots\) is a product made out of an infinite number of terms, its result is equal to a finite number that is \(0\).
Agree?
You are certainly not telling us that the result of an infinite product can never be calculated because due to the number of terms being endless there is no end to the process of calculation? I hope that's not what you're trying to tell us.
How do we know that the result of this infinite product is \(0\)? We know it's \(0\) because we know that all of its partial products are equal to \(0\). What this means is that we can calculate the result of an infinite product by looking at its partial products.
So yes, I know full well we're dealing with an infinite product (and not merely its partial products.) But I also know that the way to calculate the result of an infinite product (or at least, to calculate its bounds) is by analyzing its partial products.
The insight is pretty basic: regardless of how many terms there are in a product of the form \(\Pi^{n} 0\), the result will always be \(0\). Now matter how big the number of terms is (indeed, even if its bigger than every finite number), the result will be \(0\).
Something similar applies to \(\frac{1}{10} \times \frac{1}{10} \times \frac{1}{10} \cdots\). Here, we can observe that every partial product has a different value. It doesn't matter how large the number of terms is (even if its larger than every finite number), the result is always different from every other partial product. This alone tells us that the result is not equal to \(0\). But there is one more thing we can observe: no matter how large the number of terms is, the result is never equal to or below \(0\). And this is what tells us that the result is greater than \(0\).
You, on the other hand, are telling us that we can get \(0\) by taking \(\frac{1}{10}\) and raising it to a sufficiently large number (namely, that of infinity.)
The point is that any product of the form \((\frac{1}{10})^n\) where \(n\) is any number greater than \(0\) is greater than \(0\). The only condition for \(n\) is to be greater than \(0\). It can be a finite number but it can also be a number larger than every finite number (i.e. an infinite number.) Either way, the result is greater than \(0\).
We know the infinite product of zeroes is zero insofar as we accept that any quantity, whether finite or infinite "zero times" is zero.
The fact that the partial product also comes to zero is a symptom of this, it's not the
reason for any quantity zero times being zero.
Anything zero times being zero is just logic - we don't need the partial product to know this - that's just a red herring.
Insofar as we analyse what we get when we
get away from partial products to their limit, we are "analysing its partial products" to "calculate the result of an infinite product" - but this "insofar" isn't very far if it's exactly what we're trying to get away from...
Btw your notation \(\Pi^{n} 0\) made me laugh
Try something like \(\prod_{n=1}^\infty{0_n}\) or probably just \(\prod_{n}^\infty{0n}\)
We know from \(\prod_{n=1}^\infty{\frac1{10_n}}\) that indeed any partial product has a different value - so that's no help, until we extrapolate the limit that it tends towards. The partial product also tells us that for any partial product there's a smaller product - forever. You
never get small enough. Anything greater than zero is too large, and the only value that you can't divide smaller is its limit: zero. So whilst the partial product
looks like it'll never ever get to zero "no matter how large the number of terms is", zero is still the only value that
could make sense - as well as just so happening to be the limit. This is even though \(\prod_{n=1}^\infty{0_n}=0\) as a separate infinite sum that just so happens to reach the same result - but doesn't mean the infinite series are the same - only that they "look like" they're different and "look like" they ought to give different answers. That's what your point is - that the partial product makes it "look like" it'll always be greater than zero. But you mistake the same to apply for infinites, which cannot yield an answer small enough unless it reaches its limit of 0. Doesn't matter how much larger you want this "infinite number" to be than any "finite number", it will never be small enough - therefore all numbers greater than zero are invalid. Only zero can be valid - I can only apologise on behalf of appearances for fooling you, sorry.
You're just not appreciating what undefinability does to what's so clearly definable
for finites only. It fucks things up at a fundamental level, and you need a certain adaptability in your assumptions to intellectually deal with the consequences of infinities.
That's the only barrier to this discussion breaking out of this otherwise infinite loop.
Magnus Anderson wrote:Silhouette wrote:If "One day Joe ate them all", and "There is an infinite line of apples", there would be always be more left to eat if the line was infinite. A contradiction.
If he ate them
all, this means he left no apple behind.
This is convenient, huh? Simply define infinity as being able to have a completed "all" like finites can. Except infinity is the opposite of that, and can't.
Let's give Joe an infinitely large mouth - he both infinitely overshoots with his bite because of the infinity of his mouth, and infinitely undershoots due to there always being infinitely more apples.
Undefined.
It's incapable of definably being completely changed or destroyed - any notion of a completed "all" is invalid.
Magnus Anderson wrote:Let's take a simpler example.
"Once upon a time, there was an infinite number of apples at some point in the universe. One day, every single one of them disappeared."
Are you telling us that the process of an infinite number of apples disappearing cannot be completed within a finite period of time (not to mention instantly)?
How about this example?
"Once upon a time, there was an infinite number of green apples at some point in the universe. One day, every single one of them changed to red."
I love magic stories!
And then what happened?! Feeling... sleepy....
