And now

While going on, this moment has some meaning(pause)

It’s really a case where is fire, the smoke is obviously divertivr
Eagles fly, easily circling the carcass not as bolulchers donut certainly

Looking for the finer things

Life bearing

(And the other one cuts in)

So what they dare not could not cross over, over there, and it appears superficially deviceive, so trite

( but the other who is a him goes:

I’d rather not let you in a little secret

And they go on like that blushing and frowning alternatively matching faces of accommodation, as a buzz is heard

They gasp

So to go on, and on the night is being too old and weary, run down.

It’s advancing

This time the he comments on the stuff going on last night and tomorrow’s , while a string of Mozart heard background music in a little summer’s night

The floor opens up to reveal a cavernous abysmal structure below, gaping musty odor and the sins through and from antiquity

Birds, all kinds suddenly shriek and out so that to dark the coming day’s night as a new day borne, freely exhaling the night, .

See how it goes?

The liberals don’t know that congress in session will again deliver a blow which certainly try to turn that day into night, and increase the coming attraction’s frightening implication:

The third man returns finally and merely expresses the current vogue, the rage,

Against the machine and quietly summons the courage to whisper:

“Carry on,( and even more slightly ) :

“Carry on as if nothing happened, nothing at all”

Among some little disturbance in the buck ushered duly out, the lights dim the curtains close.

There is some faint clap from the orchestra, the solo violinist bows, and the two characters dressed in brocade and pears around their sundry necks, exit out parroting something inaudible.

The characters come back!

Irony upon ironic twists and turns.

What’s going on?

heck if I would want to find out even if I could, the stakes are very singularly high, but will review in a timely manner.

. Who you talking to foo?

Wikipedia

Neal Cassady

Neal Leon Cassady (February 8, 1926 – February 4, 1968) was a major figure of the Beat Generation of the 1950s and the psychedelic and counterculture movements of the 1960s.

Neal Cassady

Born
Neal Leon Cassady
February 8, 1926
Salt Lake City, Utah, U.S.
Died
February 4, 1968 (aged 41)
San Miguel de Allende, Mexico
Occupation
Author, poet
Genre
Beat poetry
Notable works
The First Third
Spouse
LuAnne Henderson (1945–1948; annulled),
Carolyn Cassady (1948–1963; divorced),[1]
Partner
Diane Hansen (1950–?),
Anne Murphy (?–1968)
Children

Cassady published only two short fragments of prose in his lifetime, but exerted considerable intellectual and stylistic influence through his conversation and correspondence. Letters, poems, and an unfinished autobiographical novel have been published since his death.

He was prominently featured as himself in the “scroll” (first draft) version of Jack Kerouac’s novel On the Road, and served as the model for the character Dean Moriarty in the 1957 version of that book. In many of Kerouac’s later books, Cassady is represented by the character Cody Pomeray. Cassady also appeared in Allen Ginsberg’s poems, and in several other works of literature by other writers.

Biography

Early years

Learn more

Cassady was born to Maude Jean (Scheuer) and Neal Marshall Cassady in Salt Lake City, Utah.[3] His mother died when he was 10, and he was raised by his alcoholic father in Denver, Colorado. Cassady spent much of his youth either living on the streets of skid row, with his father, or in reform school.

As a youth, Cassady was repeatedly involved in petty crime. He was arrested for car theft when he was 14, for shoplifting and car theft when he was 15, and for car theft and fencing stolen property when he was 16.

In 1941, the 15-year-old Cassady met Justin W. Brierly, a prominent Denver educator.[4] Brierly was well known as a mentor of promising young men and was impressed by Cassady’s intelligence. Over the next few years, Brierly took an active role in Cassady’s life. Brierly helped admit Cassady to East High School where he taught Cassady as a student, encouraged and supervised his reading, and found employment for him. Cassady continued his criminal activities, however, and was repeatedly arrested from 1942 to 1944; on at least one of these occasions, he was released by law enforcement into Brierly’s safekeeping. In June 1944, Cassady was arrested for possession of stolen goods and served 11 months of a one-year prison sentence. Brierly and he actively exchanged letters during this period, even through Cassady’s intermittent incarcerations; this correspondence represents Cassady’s earliest surviving letters.[5] Some authors have suggested that Brierly may have also been responsible for Cassady’s first homosexual experience.[6][verify]

Personal life
Edit
See caption
1944 Denver mug shot of Cassady
In October 1945, after being released from prison, Cassady married 16-year-old Lu Anne Henderson.[7] In 1946, the couple traveled to New York City to visit their friend, Hal Chase, another protégé of Brierly’s. While visiting Chase at Columbia University, Cassady met Jack Kerouac and Allen Ginsberg.[8] Although Cassady did not attend Columbia, he soon became friends with them and their acquaintances, some of whom later became members of the Beat Generation. While in New York, Cassady persuaded Kerouac to teach him to write fiction. Cassady’s second wife, Carolyn, has stated, “Neal, having been raised in the slums of Denver amongst the world’s lost men, determined to make more of himself, to become somebody, to be worthy and respected. His genius mind absorbed every book he could find, whether literature, philosophy, or science. Jack had a formal education, which Neal envied, but intellectually he was more than a match for Jack, and they enjoyed long discussions on every subject.”[9]

Carolyn Robinson met Cassady in 1947, while she was studying for her master’s in theater arts at the University of Denver.[10] Five weeks after Lu Anne’s departure, Neal got an annulment from Lu Anne and married Carolyn, on April 1, 1948. Carolyn’s book, Off the Road: Twenty Years with Cassady, Kerouac and Ginsberg (1990), details her marriage to Cassady and recalls him as “the archetype of the American Man”.[11] Cassady’s sexual relationship with Ginsberg lasted off and on for the next 20 years.[12]

During this period, Cassady worked for the Southern Pacific Railroad and kept in touch with his “Beat” acquaintances, even as they became increasingly different philosophically.

The couple eventually had three children and settled down in a ranch house in Monte Sereno, California, 50 miles south of San Francisco, where Kerouac and Ginsberg sometimes visited.[13] This home, built in 1954 with money from a settlement from Southern Pacific Railroad for a train-related accident, was demolished in August 1997.[14] In 1950, Cassady entered into a marriage with Diane Hansen, a young model who was pregnant with his child, Curtis Hansen.[15]

Cassady traveled cross-country with both Kerouac and Ginsberg on multiple occasions, including the trips documented in Kerouac’s On the Road.

Role of drugs
Edit
Following an arrest in 1958 for offering to share a small amount of marijuana with an undercover agent at a San Francisco nightclub, Cassady served a two-year sentence at California’s San Quentin State Prison in Marin County. After his release in June 1960, he struggled to meet family obligations, and Carolyn divorced him when his parole period expired in 1963. Carolyn stated that she was looking to relieve Cassady of the burden of supporting a family, but “this was a mistake and removed the last pillar of his self-esteem”.[16]

After the divorce, in 1963, Cassady shared an apartment with Allen Ginsberg and Beat poet Charles Plymell, at 1403 Gough Street, San Francisco.[citation needed]

Cassady first met author Ken Kesey during the summer of 1962; he eventually became one of the Merry Pranksters, a group that formed around Kesey in 1964, who were vocal proponents of the use of psychedelic drugs.[citation needed]

Travels and death
Edit
During 1964, Cassady served as the main driver of the bus named Furthur on the iconic first half of the journey from San Francisco to New York, which was immortalized by Tom Wolfe’s book, The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test (1968). Cassady appears at length in a documentary film about the Merry Pranksters and their cross-country trip, Magic Trip (2011), directed by Alex Gibney.

In January 1967, Cassady traveled to Mexico with fellow prankster George “Barely Visible” Walker and Cassady’s longtime girlfriend Anne Murphy. In a beachside house just south of Puerto Vallarta, Jalisco, they were joined by Barbara Wilson and Walter Cox. All-night storytelling, speed drives in Walker’s Lotus Elan, and the use of LSD made for a classic Cassady performance — “like a trained bear,” Carolyn Cassady once said. Cassady was beloved for his ability to inspire others to love life, yet at rare times he was known to express regret over his wild life, especially as it affected his family. At one point, Cassady took Cox, then 19, aside and told him: “[T]wenty years of fast living — there’s just not much left, and my kids are all screwed up. Don’t do what I have done.”[citation needed]

During the next year, Cassady’s life became less stable, and the pace of his travels more frenetic. He left Mexico in May, traveling to San Francisco, Denver, New York City, and points in between. Cassady then returned to Mexico in September and October (stopping in San Antonio, on the way to visit his oldest daughter, who had just given birth to his first grandchild), visited Ken Kesey’s Oregon farm in December, and spent the New Year with Carolyn at a friend’s house near San Francisco. Finally, in late January 1968, Cassady returned to Mexico once again.

On February 3, 1968, Cassady attended a wedding party in San Miguel de Allende, Guanajuato, Mexico. After the party, he went walking along a railroad track to reach the next town, but passed out in the cold and rainy night wearing nothing but a T-shirt and jeans. In the morning, he was found in a coma by the tracks, reportedly by Anton Black, later a professor at El Paso Community College, who carried Cassady over his shoulders to the local post office building. Cassady was then transported to the closest hospital, where he died a few hours later on February 4, aged 41.

The exact cause of Cassady’s death remains uncertain. Those who attended the wedding party confirm that he took an unknown quantity of secobarbital, a powerful barbiturate sold under the brand name Seconal. The physician who performed the autopsy wrote simply, “general congestion in all systems.” When interviewed later, the physician stated that he was unable to give an accurate report because Cassady was a foreigner and there were drugs involved. “Exposure” is commonly cited as his cause of death, although his widow believes he may have died of kidney failure.[17]

Children
Edit
Cassady has five known children: Robert William Hyatt Jr. (1945), Cathleen Joanne Cassady (1948), Jami Cassady Ratto (1949), Curtis W. Hansen (1950), and John Allen Cassady (1951). Robert, son of Neal Cassady and Maxine Beam, is an artist working in Arvada, Colorado. In February 2017, he was featured in Westword magazine.[18] Cathleen, known as Cathy, is the mother of the only grandchild Neal met. Cathy, Jami, and John keep a website in memory of their parents and parents’ “beat” friends.[19][20]

Curt, born from his marriage with Diana Hansen, died April 30, 2014, aged 63. He was one of the co-founders of radio station WEBE 108, in Bridgeport, Connecticut.[21]

Writing style and influence

Last edited 1 month ago by Omnipaedista

Wikipedia

Electric Kool-Aid acid test noted.

Bring in’ back those good times

Falling down. Gotta move on travel on and please don’t look into the mirror not quit yet.

It really does take two. No mapper points of reference. Always recoverable , Golgotha lostness accepted for ever says that great man Kerouac.

His daughter died very young she took off on the toad the same way, Jan her name was , he disowned her don’t know why but later tests think dna proved it but have an idea that it was a stunt on his part so irresponsibility could not deflect a bad image.

Scenes from a life.

Will describe the first, well the first miracle that noted a special something on my part, but recounting that one in a stream of coincidences later.

Looked at Erica Jung as some comfort blanketing a mini tumolteous set of pointillistic abstraction to closely watched, as trains scream by shrill the blackness of the night, tearing oreverbally the scent of shaded darkness to reveal the orange grey ness of rising day.

Time to go but see billy, if she will return again once more to fair.

The New House is almost a major character in my story.
I am the product of long corridors, empty sunlit rooms,
upstair indoor silences, attics explored in solitude,
distant noises of gurgling cisterns and pipes,
and the noise of wind under the tiles. Also, of endless books.

—Surprised by Joy

The circle realized by who, changed everything, as did the square, where ch got cut by a double edged knife, firming to triangles which formed the triangle fro which evolved the calculus and then that go beseek, maddened those who could not reverse engineer to the originally intended one piece

The dialectic was born of two parallel squares from a seeming identical nod, that lost the apologetics searched a new language resourced from the asiomatic self reflection of what already was inscribed
that was a positive development few believed in, so nature reacted by paralleling that reflection through revised means of prototypical reproduction onto of the realm of a consecutively rebuilt box, that children possessed in their very literal view of representing reality as an eternally given objective representation of eternity.

So was Jesus and Nietzhe mad, or angry in their similar, albeit reflexively mirrored elementary but complex reduction of what they saw and understood to mean by what they alluded to?

The blocks of the sqare post script I Ely fit like a jig saw saw the squares cut into to, once parellel to prove length wise, the other through the hypothenuse to form the hypothetical investigation, and all within the freedom given to choose.

Children are not irresponsible in their choices, hence, can not ever be blamed until in full possession of the Final Cut.

Then all parts will appearently and really fit, exposing the dilemma as solve by the cubists.

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Search
PRIMARY MENUSKIP TO CONTENT
Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness
Integrated Information Theory (IIT) offers an explanation for the nature and source of consciousness. Initially proposed by Giulio Tononi in 2004, it claims that consciousness is identical to a certain kind of information, the realization of which requires physical, not merely functional, integration, and which can be measured mathematically according to the phi metric.

The theory attempts a balance between two different sets of convictions. On the one hand, it strives to preserve the Cartesian intuitions that experience is immediate, direct, and unified. This, according to IIT’s proponents and its methodology, rules out accounts of consciousness such as functionalism that explain experience as a system operating in a certain way, as well as ruling out any eliminativist theories that deny the existence of consciousness. On the other hand, IIT takes neuroscientific descriptions of the brain as a starting point for understanding what must be true of a physical system in order for it to be conscious. (Most of IIT’s developers and main proponents are neuroscientists.) IIT’s methodology involves characterizing the fundamentally subjective nature of consciousness and positing the physical attributes necessary for a system to realize it.

In short, according to IIT, consciousness requires a grouping of elements within a system that have physical cause-effect power upon one another. This in turn implies that only reentrant architecture consisting of feedback loops, whether neural or computational, will realize consciousness. Such groupings make a difference to themselves, not just to outside observers. This constitutes integrated information. Of the various groupings within a system that possess such causal power, one will do so maximally. This local maximum of integrated information is identical to consciousness.

IIT claims that these predictions square with observations of the brain’s physical realization of consciousness, and that, where the brain does not instantiate the necessary attributes, it does not generate consciousness. Bolstered by these apparent predictive successes, IIT generalizes its claims beyond human consciousness to animal and artificial consciousness. Because IIT identifies the subjective experience of consciousness with objectively measurable dynamics of a system, the degree of consciousness of a system is measurable in principle; IIT proposes the phi metric to quantify consciousness.

Table of Contents

The Main Argument
Cartesian Commitments
Axioms
Postulates
The Identity of Consciousness
Some Predictions
Characterizing the Argument
The Phi Metric
The Main Idea
Some Issues of Application
Situating the Theory
Some Prehistory
IIT’s Additional Support
IIT as Sui Generis
Relation to Panpsychism
Relation to David Chalmers
Implications
The Spectrum of Consciousness
IIT and Physics
Artificial Consciousness
Constraints on Structure/Architecture
Relation to “Silent Neurons”
Objections
The Functionalist Alternative
Rejecting Cartesian Commitments
Case Study: Access vs. Phenomenal Consciousness
Challenging IIT’s Augmentation of Naturalistic Ontology
Aaronson’s Reductio ad Absurdum
Searle’s Objection
References and Further Reading

  1. The Main Argument

IIT takes certain features of consciousness to be unavoidably true. Rather than beginning with the neural correlates of consciousness (NCC) and attempting to explain what about these sustains consciousness, IIT begins with its characterization of experience itself, determines the physical properties necessary for realizing these characteristics, and only then puts forward a theoretical explanation of consciousness, as identical to a special case of information instantiated by those physical properties. “The theory provides a principled account of both the quantity and quality of an individual experience… and a calculus to evaluate whether a physical system is conscious” (Tononi and Koch, 2015).

a. Cartesian Commitments

IIT takes Descartes very seriously. Descartes located the bedrock of epistemology in the knowledge of our own existence given to us by our thought. “I think, therefore I am” reflects an unavoidable certainty: one cannot deny one’s own existence as a thinker even if one’s particular thoughts are in error. For IIT, the relevance of this insight lies in its application to consciousness. Whatever else one might claim about consciousness, one cannot deny its existence.

i. Axioms

IIT takes consciousness as primary. Before speculating on the origins or the necessary and sufficient conditions for consciousness, IIT gives a characterization of what consciousness means. The theory advances five axioms intended to capture just this. Each axiom articulates a dimension of experience that IIT regards as self-evident.

First, following from the fundamental Cartesian insight, is the axiom of existence. Consciousness is real and undeniable; moreover, a subject’s consciousness has this reality intrinsically; it exists from its own perspective.

Second, consciousness has composition. In other words, each experience has structure. Color and shape, for example, structure visual experience. Such structure allows for various distinctions.

Third is the axiom of information: the way an experience is distinguishes it from other possible experiences. An experience specifies; it is specific to certain things, distinct from others.

Fourth, consciousness has the characteristic of integration. The elements of an experience are interdependent. For example, the particular colors and shapes that structure a visual conscious state are experienced together. As we read these words, we experience the font-shape and letter-color inseparably. We do not have isolated experiences of each and then add them together. This integration means that consciousness is irreducible to separate elements. Consciousness is unified.

Fifth, consciousness has the property of exclusion. Every experience has borders. Precisely because consciousness specifies certain things, it excludes others. Consciousness also flows at a particular speed.

ii. Postulates

In isolation, these axioms may seem trivial or overlapping. IIT labels them axioms precisely because it takes them to be obviously true. IIT does not present them in isolation. Rather, they motivate postulates. Sometimes the IIT literature refers to phenomenological axioms and ontological postulates. Each axiom leads to a corresponding postulate identifying a physical property. Any conscious system must possess these properties.

First, the existence of consciousness implies a system of mechanisms with a particular cause-effect power. IIT regards existence as inextricable from causality: for something to exist, it must be able to make a difference to other things, and vice versa. (What would it even mean for a thing to exist in the absence of any causal power whatsoever?) Because consciousness exists from its own perspective, the implied system of mechanisms must do more than simply have causal power; it must have cause-effect power upon itself.

Second, the compositional nature of consciousness implies that its system’s mechanistic elements must have the capacity to combine, and that those combinations have cause-effect power.

Third, because consciousness is informative, it must specify, or distinguish one experience from others. IIT calls the cause-effect powers of any given mechanism within a system its cause-effect repertoire. The cause-effect repertoires of all the system’s mechanistic elements taken together, it calls its cause-effect structure. This structure, at any given point, is in a particular state. In complex structures, the number of possible states is very high. For a structure to instantiate a particular state is for it to specify that state. The specified state is the particular way that the system is making a difference to itself.

Fourth, consciousness’s integration into a unified whole implies that the system must be irreducible. In other words, its parts must be interdependent. This in turn implies that every mechanistic element must have the capacity to act as a cause on the rest of the system and to be affected by the rest of the system. If a system can be divided into two parts without affecting its cause-effect structure, it fails to satisfy the requirement of this postulate.

Fifth, the exclusivity of the borders of consciousness implies that the state of a conscious system must be definite. In physical terms, the various simultaneous subgroupings of mechanisms in a system have varying cause-effect structures. Of these, only one will have a maximally irreducible cause-effect structure. This is called the maximally irreducible conceptual structure, or MICS. Others will have smaller cause-effect structures, at least when reduced to non-redundant elements. Precisely this is the conscious state.

b. The Identity of Consciousness

IIT accepts the Cartesian conviction that consciousness has immediate, self-evident properties, and outlines the implications of these phenomenological axioms for conscious physical systems. This characterization does not exhaustively describe the theoretical ambition of IIT. The ontological postulates concerning physical systems do not merely articulate necessities, or even sufficiencies, for realizing consciousness. The claim is much stronger than this. IIT identifies consciousness with a system’s having the physical features that the postulates describe. Each conscious state is a maximally irreducible conceptual structure, which just is and can only be a system of irreducibly interdependent physical parts whose causal interaction constitutes the integration of information.

An example may help to clarify the nature of IIT’s explanation of consciousness. Our experience of a cue ball integrates its white color and spherical shape, such that these elements are inseparably fused. The fusion of these elements constitutes the structure of the experience: the experience is composed of them. The nature of the experience informs us about whiteness and spherical shape in a way that distinguishes it from other possible experiences, such as of a blue cube of chalk. This is just a description of the phenomenology of a simple experience (perhaps necessarily awkward, because it articulates the self-evident). Our brain generates the experience through neurons physically communicating with one another in systems linked by cause-effect power. IIT interprets this physical communication as the integration of information, according to the various constraints laid out in the postulates. The neurobiology and phenomenology converge.

Theories of consciousness need to account for what is sometimes termed the “binding problem.” This concerns the unity of conscious experience. Even a simple experience like viewing a cue ball unites different elements such as color, shape, and size. Any theory of consciousness will need to make sense of how this happens. IIT’s account of the integration of information may be understood as a response to this problem.

According to IIT, the physical state of any conscious system must converge with phenomenology; otherwise the kind of information generated could not realize the axiomatic properties of consciousness. We can understand this by contrasting two kinds of information. First, there is Shannon information: When a digital camera takes a picture of a cue ball, the photodiodes operate in causal isolation from one another. This process does generate information; specifically, it generates observer-relative information. That is, the camera generates the information of an image of a cue ball for anyone looking at that photograph. The information that is the image of the cue ball is therefore relative to the observer; such information is called Shannon information. Because the elements of the system are causally isolated, the system does not make a difference to itself. Accordingly, although the camera gives information to an observer, it does not generate that information for itself. By contrast, consider what IIT refers to as intrinsic information: Unlike the digital camera’s photodiodes, the brain’s neurons do communicate with one another through physical cause and effect; the brain does not simply generate observer-relative information, it integrates intrinsic information. This information from its own perspective just is the conscious state of the brain. The physical nature of the digital camera does not conform to IIT’s postulates and therefore does not have consciousness; the physical nature of the brain, at least in certain states, does conform to IIT’s postulates, and therefore does have consciousness.

To identify consciousness with such physical integration of information constitutes an ontological claim. The physical postulates do not describe one way or even the best way to realize the phenomenology of consciousness; the phenomenology of consciousness is one and the same as a system having the properties described by the postulates. It is even too weak to say that such systems give rise to or generate consciousness. Consciousness is fundamental to these systems in the same way as mass or charge is basic to certain particles.

i. Some Predictions

IIT’s conception of consciousness as mechanisms systematically integrating information through cause and effect lends itself to quantification. The more complex the MICS, the higher the level of consciousness: the corresponding metric is phi. Sometimes the IIT literature uses the term “prediction” to refer to implications of the theory whose falsifiability is a matter of controversy. This section will focus on more straightforward cases of prediction, where the evidence is consistent with IIT’s claims. These cases provide corroborative evidence that enhance the plausibility of IIT.

Deep sleep states are less experientially rich than waking ones. IIT predicts, therefore, that such sleep states will have lower phi values than waking states. For this to be true, analysis of the brain during these contrasting states would have to show a disparity in the systematic complexity of non-redundant mechanisms. On IIT, this disparity of MICS complexity directly implies a disparity in the amount of conscious integrated information, because the MICS is identical to the conscious state. The neuroscientific findings bear out this prediction.

IIT cites similar evidence from the study of patients with brain damage. For example, we already know that among vegetative patients, there are some whose brain scans indicate that they can hear and process language: When researchers prompt such patients to think about playing tennis, the appropriate areas of the brain become activated. Other vegetative patients do not respond this way. Naturally, this suggests that the former have a richer degree of consciousness than the latter. When analyzed according to IIT’s theory, the former have a higher phi metric than the latter; once again, IIT has made a prediction that receives empirical confirmation. IIT also claims that findings in the analysis of patients under anesthesia corroborate its claims.

In all these cases, one of two things happens. First, as consciousness fades, cortical activity may become less global. This reversion to local cortical activity constitutes a loss of integration: The system no longer is communicating across itself in as complex a way as it had. Second, as consciousness fades, cortical activity may remain global, but become stereotypical, consisting in numerous redundant cause-effect mechanisms, such that the informational achievement of the system is reduced: a loss of information. As information either becomes less integrated or becomes reduced, consciousness fades, which IIT takes as empirical support of its theory of consciousness as integrated information.

c. Characterizing the Argument

IIT combines Cartesian commitments with claims about engineering that it interprets, in part by citing corroborative neuroscientific evidence, as identifying the nature of consciousness. This borrows from recognizable traditions in the field of consciousness studies, but the structure of the argument is novel. While IIT’s proponents strive for clarity in the exposition of their work by breaking it down into the simpler elements of axioms, propositions, and identity claims, the nature of the relations between these parts remains largely implicit in the IIT literature. To evaluate the explanatory success or failure of IIT, it should prove helpful to attempt an explication of these logical relations. This requires characterizing the relationship of the axioms with the postulates, and of the identity claims with the axioms, postulates, and supporting neuroscientific evidence.

The axioms, of course, count
© Copyright Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy and its Authors | ISSN 2161-0002

…partial copy

The other part?

Well will return there, but how minimal above suppositions mean in that scheme of things, when primal urges so deductively, reduced unlike as they would seductively?

Feeding off on some such is the utility belonging to shamans and such, but let us not goi into that not yet, anyhow.

Exit.s

No

I like that maximally irreducible conceptual structure a.k.a. complexity :wink:

But I think instead of calling it conceptual we should call it consent. Because the cause-effect thingy. Making a difference and what not.

Guess it’s too late now.

Not to some concern that such would indicate a belated pessimism, not melancholy , a reflex action which echos a universal angst, not nearly relevant to dis-content~connect.

(Heard screams from underground, gnashing of teeth, tearing of hair, and of course: the eye.)

“When the Lamb broke the fifth seal, I saw under the altar the souls of all who had been martyred for the word of God and for being faithful in their testimony. They shouted to the Lord and said, “O Sovereign Lord, holy and true, how long before you judge the people who belong to this world and avenge our blood for what they have done to us?” Then a white robe was given to each of them. And they were told to rest a little longer until the full number of their brothers and sisters—their fellow servants of Jesus who were to be martyred—had joined them.”
‭‭Revelation‬ ‭6‬:‭9‬-‭11‬ ‭NLT‬‬
bible.com/bible/116/rev.6.9-11.NLT

Read it all.

maximal

for future reference

As that future is here, now

.
Ominous? thrilling? enthralling? unknown…?

All of the above and then some, depending on the mood. Blue is my favorite as well’

“ Ominous? thrilling? enthralling? unknown”

Ominous goes with dark colors, greys, black, deepest brown;

Thrilling with bright reds and yellows , so is enthralling, for the difference in hues could paint the semantic shift between light reflections,

But the dark navy blue and azure mix would well represent the depth of the unknown.

That blues are my favorite genre in music as well, as in painting, with the impressions cast by Monet, Suarez, gogain’s starry night illuminating a lonely cafe,

So my answer is wrapped in mystery.

The fuepturrreu is mysteriously wrapped, congruent to how God works in mysterious ways.

Unknown, mysterious, like , almost, allowing us to try to figure and briefly comment with baby strokes on an immense canvas, drawn as a black and white sketch then overlay it in color, while retaining the sketch, like the color was a superfluous freeze added to an ancient well modulated construction, left better unfinished.