Bell's Theorem - a paradox in reality

I don’t really know what you’re talking about. You linked to a science-denying Christian apologist YouTube video to either explain or prove something to someone else. But linking to a science denying apologist channel to explain science is like linking to a Nazi channel to explain Judaism.

Like, sure, maybe this one particular video has this one particular Nazi saying correct things about Jews (maybe he’s just relaying a biblical story about the Jews time in Egypt or something), but that’s not a source you should be using in discussions about Jews, and EVERYTHING they say would have to be cross checked with more reliable sources before it could be even considered.

I’m not interested in spending my time watching hours of pseudo science apologetics, so I’ll have to decline your offer

Thank you for wearing your prejudice on your sleeve like a badge of honor.

Here’s my badge of honor:

<><

Now we BOTH have badges!!

Twinsies!!!

This isn’t a clever gotcha. “I am prejudiced against learning science from explicitly anti science sources.” Absolutely I am, I stand by that, and any half reasonable person should share that view.

We only have so much time in this earth to learn and reason and think, and if we have absolutely no prejudices where we get our information from, we’d spend an awful lot of time learning an awful lot of false shit.

Reasonable people should have that sort of prejudice.

Honestly, I know you think I’m going to change my mind, but the actual effect you’re having is causing me to lose respect for you. I won’t—I know you have insights and knowledge regardless of your prejudices… but you are off on this one. Dead off. Give up.

I don’t think you’re the type of person to change your mind, I’m just expressing my thoughts. If those thoughts I just shared lost respect from you, then I don’t value respect from you, because that post didn’t have a word out of place.

If you want to spend your finite time on this planet being completely indiscriminate in what you spend time reading and learning, that’s your right, but you will undoubtedly spend an unreasonable time reading and learning absolute tripe, and I won’t join you in that.

If you’re still curious about what spin is, I ran across this video today and it reminded me of this thread

youtu.be/pWlk1gLkF2Y

Is this wrong?

energy=mass(speed of light)^2

electromagnetism=gravity(square root of mass)

since gravity & speed of light are the same

together with the reasoning behind why the gravitational field and the magnetic field are different

Yeah looks wrong to me.

Gravity is the fact that everything in existence is “one thing” and connected ultimately all the way down. As quantas of information or entanglement or the fabric of reality, however you want to conceptualize it. All things are part of one thing. Therefore it is the case that when this “one thing” (existence itself) is stretched out like it is in our reality, there exists within the component parts a natural tendency toward reuniting back together, pulling back together into the singular whole (pre-big bang moment).

Logically from this fact it also follows that the more of reality that occurs within a given chunk/piece of existence, the more strongly will be this tendency to pull-reunite back together into the original form. When you stretch out a piece of something stretchy, like a sheet of rubber, and imagine in the sheet there are clumps of more concentrated rubber and other areas of very thin rubber with not much there. The thin areas will experience less ‘pull’ compared to the thicker areas because the thicker areas have more matter/mass there to actually generate the pulling force, the tension.

Reality is just like this, which is why the more massive something is the more “gravity” it seems to have. Basically when you have more of reality clumped together in one place you see more manifestation of this basic underlying effect/logic of pulling back together tendency which occurs naturally in anything that becomes stretched out beyond its original shape.

Yeah, looks like the harmonic triad sounding off in a pre calculation effort to achieve a unitary field.

I have to put it together with something I saw that had multiple equal signs in it, but now I don’t remember where I saw that.

I’m sure the real nerds have it figured out already.

Yeah but did they figure out the configuration of their figuring we kinda of knowing that?

That’s probably a good thing if it’s happened/happening, but it could add an extra measure of uncertainty to the equation, who but Gos would know that.

Of course, this tech already exists. We just aren’t allowed to know about it yet.

The military industrial complex needs to covertly use it to expand its power and wealth first, only after that will it allow a highly parsed-down, commercialized version of the technology to become known to the masses.

But then ‘Empire’ presupposed holding power to guarantee the standards that have been associated with living up to par.

The cosmetic appeal of such standards are particularly critical when the process of normalized relations are proceeding in the only way possible globally, that is, to outsource such over borders, to normalize the perception that other nations can equally control and profit from the empire’s know how, technologically , culturally and other wise.

The reality is different. Methods of control have been internalized far too long, as the industrial society has been transformed into an informational one, where appearances seem to be the mover and shaker of the way power is distributed in the world.

The paradox deepens as the national-international reality of the mix creates these illusions.

For example, the phenomenal Japanese miracle, when truly looked at, shows an incredible use of nativity that US economic interests don’t ‘buy-into’ them , with accumulated, or impromptedly raised and printed capital to regain control of her markets. The same goes for Indian Casinos, the method of running them the silent partnership of Vegas bosses iIS obviously an extended firm of hedging interests and techniques of running gambling that have been internalized since time immemorial.

Only war trade and other wise can open this paradox to true light.

Flannel. You don’t see what is right in front of you.

The physics you know is propaganda.

C^2 is by definition faster than light. C is light.

If nothing can move faster than it, then how can it be squared?

You live in a big lie making fun of you at your expense.

I’ll tell you another funny thing about physics equations. The operators are arbitrary.

Force equals mass times excelleration could also be force equals mass divided by acceleration …

The output would be different but the answers would still be consistent.

(Here is an eye opener to discover within the flow of the artificiality discussed by ‘basic language’ -that is pointed out in this sun level ‘discovery’ , and was really searching through dna sequencing as an example to connect vanity, in both, the psychological and philosophical sense to…

Morphological bubbles which when sliced into an observable specimen, can create the impressive genylogically based perrimism on the short term. However such imminent thinking, ex-post facto, from the point of view of a doubling expression of factual ‘arrival’ to the point that a new model can be immediately be compared to nietzche’s last man narrative, ,

Where such model, morally and aesthetically relate to permanent gynological roots,

Can not project or predict an objectively permanent and uninterrupted flow: and the seeming modern flow then related to the hidden aspects of the relationship between vanity and mere contemporaneous jealousy.’( my quotes)

To vit :

“arXiv Vanity renders academic papers from arXiv as responsive web pages so you don’t have to squint at a PDF

View this paper on arXiv
The Scope and Generality of Bell’s Theorem

James Owen Weatherall
Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science
University of California, Irvine, CA 92697
ABSTRACT

I present what might seem to be a local, deterministic model of the EPR-Bohm experiment, inspired by recent work by Joy Christian, that appears at first blush to be in tension with Bell-type theorems. I argue that the model ultimately fails to do what a hidden variable theory needs to do, but that it is interesting nonetheless because the way it fails helps clarify the scope and generality of Bell-type theorems. I formulate and prove a minor proposition that makes explicit how Bell-type theorems rule out models of the sort I describe here.
1 INTRODUCTION

Bell-type theorems are usually understood to rule out a class of hidden variable interpretations of quantum mechanics that are, in a certain precise sense, local and deterministic. These theorems come in a variety of forms, with different characterizations of what local and deterministic are meant to amount to. In the simplest case, Bell-type theorems show that any hidden variable model satisfying some set of conditions fails to agree with the quantum mechanical predictions for the outcomes of a simple experiment, often called the EPR-Bohm experiment. When one performs the suggested experiments, meanwhile, the results agree with quantum mechanics. The upshot appears to be that no local, deterministic hidden variable model can correctly reproduce the measurement outcomes of a certain class of experiments.1
In this paper, I discuss a geometrical model of EPR-Bohm experiments that appears, at least at first blush, to get around Bell-type theorems.2 The model offers an explicit representation of the states of the particles in an EPR-Bohm experiment. It is manifestly local and fully deterministic. And it appears to yield the correct measurement outcomes, as predicted by quantum mechanics. As one would expect given what I have just said, the model I will describe differs from the kind of system Bell seemed to have in mind in several important ways—ways, I might add, that are physically motivated by the EPR-Bohm experiment itself.3
Unfortunately, the model is not ultimately satisfactory, in ways I will be able to spell out clearly later in the paper. But it seems to me that it fails in an interesting way. The model draws attention to just what criteria a local, deterministic hidden variable model would need to satisfy in order to accurately reproduce the results of an EPR-Bohm experiment. The particular way in which the present model fails to meet those criteria speaks to the generality of Bell-type theorems. Taking the model as a guide, I will formulate and prove a minor proposition to the effect that a class of hidden variable models similar in a certain respect to the one I describe cannot reproduce the EPR-Bohm measurement results, properly understood. The proposition follows as a corollary of a version of Bell’s theorem. This means that models of the type I will describe are already ruled out by Bell-type considerations, despite the apparent differences between the model I will discuss and the kind of hidden variable models with which Bell-type theorems seem to be concerned.4
It is worth emphasizing up front that I do not take the main proposition of this paper to be a significant new contribution. Indeed, there is a strong sense in which the result, though it might appear to be a generalization of standard Bell-type theorems, simply is Bell’s theorem, or even a slight weakening of it. The goal of this paper is instead to show why Bell-type theorems really do have the scope and generality standardly ascribed to them, by explaining how a particular strategy for getting around Bell-type theorems goes wrong. The main proposition, then, is just an attempt to re-phrase Bell’s theorem in a way that makes the connection between Bell-type hidden variable models and these alternative, allegedly local and deterministic ‘‘generalized’’ hidden variable models fully transparent.5
The paper will proceed as follows. I will begin by describing the EPR-Bohm setup and stating the version of Bell’s theorem that I will focus on here. Then I will present the model that will be the focus of the present discussion. I will show that it is local and deterministic, but that it nonetheless seems to reproduce the quantum mechanical predictions for the EPR-Bohm experiment. In the penultimate section, I will describe what goes wrong with the model and then formulate and prove the no-go result described above. I will conclude with some remarks concerning the generality of Bell-type theorems.
2 THE EPR-BOHM EXPERIMENT AND A BELL-TYPE THEOREM

The version of Bell’s theorem I will discuss here is based on an experimental configuration known as the EPR-Bohm setup, which involves two spin 1/2 particles,
A
and
B
, traveling in opposite directions. One assumes that the pair initially has vanishing total spin, which means that the quantum mechanical spin state for the system,
|
Ψ

, is an entangled superposition often called the “singlet state.” A natural way to express the singlet state is in terms of the eigenvectors of the spin operator about an arbitrary unit vector
n
. The spin operator about
n
is given by
σ

n
, where
σ
is the Pauli spin “vector,” defined by
σ

(
σ
x
,
σ
y
,
σ
z
)
, with
σ
x
,
σ
y
,
σ
z
the Pauli spin matrices.6 These eigenvectors can be written in the standard Dirac notation so that
σ

n
|
n
,
±

±
|
n
,
±

. The singlet state of the two-particle system can then be expressed by
|
Ψ

1

2
(
|
n
,
+

A

|
n
,


B

|
n
,


A

|
n
,
+

B
)
,
where the
A
and
B
subscripts indicate membership in the Hilbert spaces associated with particles
A
and
B
respectively.
The experiment consists of two measurements, one on each particle, performed at remote locations by two observers, Alice and Bob. Alice and Bob each choose a unit vector,
a
and
b
respectively, and then perform measurements of the spin of their assigned particle about the chosen vector (suppose Alice is measuring particle
A
and Bob is measuring particle
B
). Simple calculations yield the following quantum mechanical predictions for the expected outcomes of these experiments. The expectation values for Alice and Bob’s individual experimental outcomes are,
E
q
.
m
.
(
A
(
a
)
)


Ψ
|
(
σ

a
)
A

I
B
|
Ψ

0
(2.1)
E
q
.
m
.
(
B
(
b
)
)


Ψ
|
I
A

(
σ

b
)
B
|
Ψ

(2.2)
Meanwhile, the expectation value of the (tensor) product of the two observables
(
σ

a
)
A

(
σ

b
)
B
, a measure of the correlation between the two measurements, is given by
E
q
.
m
.
(
A
(
a
)
,
B
(
b
)
)


Ψ
|
(
σ

a
)
A

(
σ

b
)
B
|
Ψ


a

b
.
(2.3)
To interpret this expectation value, it is useful to note in particular that if Alice and Bob choose to perform their measurements about orthogonal vectors, their outcomes should not exhibit any correlation at all (they are equally likely to get the same results as opposite results). Conversely, if Alice and Bob choose the same vector, their measurement results should be perfectly anti-correlated (any time Alice yields +1, Bob necessarily will yield -1, and vice versa). These predictions are well-corroborated by experiment.
Bell-type theorems are intended to rule out the possibility that the results of EPR-Bohm experiments can be recovered from a model that somehow represents the “complete” state of the two-particle system in such a way that the results of Alice and Bob’s measurements can be understood to be local and deterministic. The strategy is to postulate that there is an unknown (hidden) variable,
λ
, such that, were one to specify the value of
λ
, the results of Alice and Bob’s respective measurements would be (a) wholly determined by
λ
and the choice of his or her measurement vector (call this “determinism”), and (b) independent of the other experimenter’s choice of measurement vector (call this “locality”). One then tries to show that no such model could correctly reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics.
This idea can be made more precise as follows. We postulate that associated with each of Alice’s and Bob’s measuring devices are “observables”
A
and
B
, where by observable we mean simply maps
A
,
B
:
S
2
×
Λ

{

1
,
1
}
that take as input (1) the unit vector about which Alice or Bob is measuring, and (2) an element
λ
of the space
Λ
of complete states of the two particle system.7 The specification
λ
of the complete state of the two-particle system is what we interpret as the hidden variable. The possible measurement results, meanwhile, are represented by the integers
±
1
, just as in the quantum mechanical case (where the possible measurement results correspond to the eigenvalues of the relevant observable).
Given such a pair of observables
A
and
B
, we can define the expectation values for Alice and Bob’s measurements by postulating some probability density
ρ
:
Λ

[
0
,
1
]
, intended to reflect our ignorance of the actual value of the hidden variable. The expectation values for Alice and Bob’s individual measurements will then be given by:8
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
)


Λ
A
(
a
,
λ
)
ρ
(
λ
)
d
λ
E
h
.
v
.
(
B
(
b
)
)


Λ
B
(
b
,
λ
)
ρ
(
λ
)
d
λ
.
The version of Bell’s theorem to be stated presently will be formulated as a constraint on the expectation value of the product of
A
and
B
,
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b
)
)


Λ
A
(
a
,
λ
)
B
(
b
,
λ
)
ρ
(
λ
)
d
λ
.
As in the quantum mechanical case, this expectation value is understood as a measure of the correlation between Alice and Bob’s measurements.
This discussion suggests the following definitions.
Definition 2.1 A (local, deterministic) hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment is an ordered quadruple
(
Λ
,
A
,
B
,
ρ
)
, where
Λ
is the set of complete states of the system,
A
,
B
:
S
2
×
Λ

{

1
,
1
}
are maps from measurement vectors and complete state specifications to measurement outcomes for Alice and Bob respectively, and
ρ
:
Λ

[
0
,
1
]
is a probability density function on the space of complete states.
Note that determinism is built into this definition, in the sense that the maps
A
and
B
are required to be well-defined as functions, which means that there is a unique measurement result associated with each specification of a measurement vector and a complete state.9 Similarly locality is encoded in the requirement that the maps
A
and
B
are functions of a single measurement vector. (A non-local model, then, would be one on which
A
and
B
were allowed to depend on both measurement vectors.)
Given these definitions, we can now state the Bell-type theorem that we will focus on in the next section. It is essentially the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt theorem.
Theorem 2.2 (Clauser et al. (1969)) Let
(
Λ
,
A
,
B
,
ρ
)
be a local, deterministic hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment. Then for any choices
a
and
a

for Alice’s detector setting, and any choices
b
and
b

for Bob’s detector setting, the expectation values for the products of Alice and Bob’s measurements must satisfy the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt inequality,
|
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b
)
)

E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b

)
)
+
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a

)
B
(
b
)
)
+
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a

)
B
(
b

)
)
|

2.
(2.4)
It is easy to verify that there are choices for
a
,
a

,
b
, and
b

such that the quantum mechanical expectation values defined in Eq. (2.3) violate this inequality, i.e., choices such that
|
E
q
.
m
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b
)
)

E
q
.
m
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b

)
)
+
E
q
.
m
.
(
A
(
a

)
B
(
b
)
)
+
E
q
.
m
.
(
A
(
a

)
B
(
b

)
)
|

This result yields an immediate corollary of Thm. 2.2.
Corollary 2.3 There does not exist a local, deterministic hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment that reproduces the quantum mechanical expectation values.
3 A LOCAL, DETERMINISTIC MODEL AFTER ALL?

As promised above, I will now explicitly exhibit what might seem to be a local, deterministic hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment. It will consist of a space
Λ
of complete states, along with a pair of local, deterministic observables
A
(
a
,
λ
)
and
B
(
b
,
λ
)
that, taken together, yield the correct quantum mechanical expectation values. Note that this means they will maximally violate the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt inequality for the same choices of
a
,
a

,
b
, and
b

as the quantum mechanical observables. As will become clear, this model is not a hidden variable model in the strict sense of definition 2.1. But one might reasonably argue that it has all of the virtues that one would hope a (generalized) hidden variable model would have.
Before I say what the model is, let me motivate it a little. The experiment whose outcomes we are trying to reproduce involves spin measurements. Quantum mechanical spin does not have a direct classical analogue, but the spin operators satisfy the same algebraic relations as rotations in three dimensional Euclidean space. This is suggestive: one might take it to imply that the right way of thinking about spin is as some sort of rotation. Following this idea, one might reason that when an experimenter measures a particle to be spin up or spin down about a given vector, she is actually measuring the orientation of the body’s rotation.
Suppose this idea is right and the experimenters are attempting to determine the orientation of each body’s rotation about freely chosen vectors
a
and
b
. How should the experimenters represent their measurement results? Clearly, one way of doing so would be to assign the numbers
±
1
to the measurement results, where, say,
+
1
is understood to correspond to spin up, which would be a counterclockwise rotation about the measurement vector (relative to a right-hand rule), and

1
would correspond to spin down and clockwise rotation. This is how the quantum mechanical expectation values come out; it is also how possible measurement results are represented in Bell-type theorems. But one might worry that this is a poor choice. Rotations in three dimensional space have more complicated algebraic and topological structure than the set
{

1
,
1
}

R
. When one represents the results of an EPR-Bohm experiment by
±
1
, this structure is lost. One might argue that it is no wonder that a hidden variable model of the type Bell describes cannot adequately represent the results of an EPR-Bohm experiment, since Bell effectively assumes a representational scheme that does not have the expressiveness necessary to capture the physics of the experiment.10
There are several ways to represent rotations (or more precisely, instantaneous states of rotation of a body) in three dimensional space that do respect the appropriate algebraic and topological properties of physical rotations. A particularly natural choice is to use antisymmetric rank 2 tensors. To see how these are a candidate for representing a body’s state of rotation, consider the following. Pick a plane and consider two linearly independent covectors in that plane. Call them
ξ
a
and
η
a
.11 Now note that there are two orientations of rotations within your chosen plane, clockwise and counterclockwise. These can be thought of as corresponding to the two ways of ordering
ξ
a
and
η
a
: one of the two orientations corresponds to a rotation that begins with
ξ
a
and sweeps in the direction of
η
a
, and the other corresponds to a rotation that begins with
η
a
and sweeps in the direction of
ξ
a
. (Think, for instance, of a clock face. Clockwise rotation corresponds to the minute hand starting at 12 and sweeping towards 1; counterclockwise orientation corresponds to the minute hand starting at 1 and sweeping towards 12.) These two ways of ordering
ξ
a
and
η
a
can be (sufficiently uniquely) represented using a pair of related antisymmetric rank 2 tensors,
1
ω
a
b

ξ
[
a
η
b
]

1
2
(
ξ
a
η
b

ξ
b
η
a
)
and
2
ω
a
b

η
[
a
ξ
b
]


1
ω
a
b
. Indeed, in three dimensions, any antisymmetric rank 2 tensor can be represented as the antisymmetric product of two vectors, and so any antisymmetric rank 2 tensor represents a rotation in just this way, as an ordering of two vectors in a plane. This means that to associate an antisymmetric rank 2 tensor with a body is to represent the body as having both a plane of rotation (or equivalently, an axis of rotation) and an orientation of rotation within that plane.12
We are thus led to the following suggestion. If one wants to adequately represent the rotation of a body about a given axis, taking full account of the algebraic and topological properties exhibited by the group of rotations in three dimensional space, one should take the observables associated with the EPR-Bohm measurement outcomes to be antisymmetric rank 2 tensors.13
,
14 This is particularly important, one might add, since we are ultimately interested in the correlation between the two systems. Hence we want to be careful to capture the full structure of what is being observed, since one might expect that the algebraic properties of rotations are important in understanding how the outcomes of two measurements of rotation will relate to one another. Of course, taking such objects as observables moves one away from a hidden variable model as defined in section 2. But that need not be a problem, especially if it turns out that all one needs to do to find a local, deterministic interpretation of quantum mechanics is to expand the mathematical playing field slightly.
Given this background, the model I propose goes as follows. Our starting point will be the manifold
R
3
, endowed with a (flat) Euclidean metric
h
a
b
. The space of constant vector fields on the manifold is isomorphic to the tangent space at any one point (by parallel transport); I will conflate these two spaces and refer to both simply as
R
3
. One can likewise define a space of (constant) antisymmetric rank 2 tensors by taking the antisymmetric product of the elements of
R
3
, as described above. I will call this space of tensors
R
3

R
3
. Note that there are precisely two volume elements (normalized antisymmetric rank 3 tensor fields) on the manifold. Call these
ϵ
a
b
c
and

ϵ
a
b
c
. We will fix a sign convention up front and take
ϵ
a
b
c
to represent the right handed volume element.15
The hidden variable space for the model will be
Λ

{
1
,

1
}
. We can then define two observables
A
,
B
:
S
2
×
Λ

R
3

R
3
as follows:
A
b
c
(
α
a
,
λ
)

λ

2
ϵ
a
b
c
α
a
B
b
c
(
β
a
,
λ
)


λ

2
ϵ
a
b
c
β
a
Note that these observables are both antisymmetric rank 2 tensors, as we wanted. They can be understood to represent rotations about the vectors
α
a
and
β
a
, as can be seen by noting that
A
b
c
(
α
a
,
λ
)
ϵ
a
b
c

α
a
and
B
b
c
(
β
a
,
λ
)
ϵ
a
b
c

β
a
. Note, too, that for a particular choice of
λ
, and for measurements about parallel vectors, we find
A
b
c
(
ξ
a
,
λ
)


B
b
c
(
ξ
a
,
λ
)
.
This means the two measurement results are always anti-correlated, as expected from the quantum mechanical case. Finally,
A
and
B
are explicitly deterministic, since given a value for the hidden variable, and given a choice of measurement vector, the observables take unique, determinate values. And they are local, in the sense that the value of the observable
A
is independent of
β
a
, and
B
is independent of
α
a
.
We assume an isotropic probability density over the space of hidden variables. This density is simply a map
ρ
:
Λ

[
0
,
1
]
that assigns equal probability to both cases. With this choice, the observables can easily be shown to yield the right single-side expectation values.16 We have for both
A
and
B
,
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
α
a
)
)

1
2
(
1

2
ϵ
a
b
c
α
a

1

2
ϵ
a
b
c
α
a
)

0
(3.1)
E
h
.
v
.
(
B
(
β
a
)
)


1
2
(
1

2
ϵ
a
b
c
β
a

1

2
ϵ
a
b
c
β
a
)

0
.
(3.2)
Hence, on average, neither body is rotating about any direction. This result is consistent with the quantum mechanical expectation values and with experiment.
Finally, we want to consider the expectation value of the product of the measurement results. This is where the algebraic properties of rotations become important, since it is at this point that one is trying to establish a relationship between two correlated, rotating bodies. But now consider the product of the outcomes:
A
b
c
(
α
a
,
λ
)
B
b
c
(
β
a
,
λ
)


λ
2
2
α
n
ϵ
n
b
c
β
m
ϵ
m
b
c


α
n
β
n
.
The associated expectation value, then, is just
E
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
α
a
)
B
(
β
a
)
)


α
a
β
a
(
1
2
+
1
2
)


α
a
β
a
,
(3.3)
again just as in the quantum mechanical case.17
,
18 With this final result, it would appear that we have written down a model of the EPR-Bohm experiment. And more, the product expectation value associated with this model will violate the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt inequality in exactly the same way as quantum mechanics—after all, it has just the same functional form.19
4 A DIAGNOSIS AND A NO-GO RESULT

What are we to make of the results of sections 2 and 3? One might argue that they do not actually conflict. Instead, the model just presented reveals that the notion of hidden variable model given by definition 2.1 is too narrow. There, a hidden variable model was defined to have two observables that were integer valued—specifically, valued by elements of the set
{

1
,
1
}
. Rotations in three dimensions, meanwhile, are a complicated business. The correlations exhibited by two rotating bodies cannot be captured in terms of a two element set. One could conclude that it is necessary to consider “observables” whose possible values reflect the full structure of rotations, as antisymmetric rank 2 tensors do. And indeed, if one does permit such observables, it would appear that one can construct a local, deterministic (generalized) hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment after all.
On this view, the model just described is not a counterexample to Bell-type theorems per se, but it does undermine their foundational importance. Bell-type theorems were of interest because they were understood to exclude a particular, appealing sort of hidden variable theory. If it were to turn out that they only applied to a limited number of those theories—ones with integer-valued observables—the standard moral of Bell-type arguments would be severely muted. There would be hope for finding a local, deterministic (generalized) hidden variable theory for quantum mechanics after all.
Unfortunately, this argument is too fast. The model I have described is not acceptable. The problem concerns what, exactly, a (generalized) hidden variable model needs to reproduce. Specifically, Eq. (3.3) does not correctly track the relevant measure of correlation between Alice and Bob’s measurement results.
To see the point, consider the following. When Alice and Bob actually run their experiments, they are perfectly entitled to record their measurement results however they choose. They can even record those results as integers
±
1
, so long as they do so systematically. If a model like the one given above is correct, then what Alice and Bob would be doing would amount to applying some map
P
from the codomain of their observables to the set
{

1
,
1
}
. Of course, there is a danger that representing their results in this way could turn out to be a poor choice. One might worry that such a recording mechanism would lose information about their measurement results. If the thing they are observing has more structure than the set
{

1
,
1
}
, then Alice and Bob would risk introducing confusing patterns into their data. Indeed, we already know that the data from EPR-Bohm experiments, standardly represented as sequences of
±
1
, do exhibit correlations that are difficult to interpret. But here is the crucial point. Whatever else is the case, the troublesome correlations that are present in EPR-Bohm data arise when the data is recorded as sequences of
±
1
. And so it is these correlations that a (generalized) hidden variable model needs to reproduce in order to be satisfactory. In other words, to show that a (generalized) hidden variable model correctly reproduces the EPR-Bohm experimental results, one needs to show that the model recovers the standard quantum mechanical expectation values after we project the generalized observables onto
{

1
,
1
}
.
So in order to determine whether the model presented above is satisfactory, we need to find a way for Alice and Bob to systematically project the relevant elements of
R
3

R
3
onto
{

1
,
1
}
. There is a principled way to do this. It is to take the integer to indicate the orientation of the rotation about the measurement vector (so,
+
1
might record counterclockwise rotation,

1
clockwise). In the present case, this representational scheme can be expressed by a family of maps defined as follows. Let
ξ
a
be a choice of measurement vector. Then there is an associated projection map
P
ξ
:
(
¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯
R
3

R
3
)
ξ

{

1
,
1
}
,20 where
(
¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯
R
3

R
3
)
ξ

R
3

R
3
is the collection of antisymmetric rank 2 tensor fields
ω
a
b
that (1) are orthogonal to
ξ
a
(i.e.,
ω
a
b
ξ
a

0
) and (2) satisfy the normalization condition
ω
a
b
ω
a
b

1
.21 The map associated with each measurement vector turns out to be unique (up to sign). For a given unit vector
ξ
a
, and for any antisymmetric rank 2 tensor field
X
a
b
in
(
¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯
R
3

R
3
)
ξ
, the map can be defined as,
P
ξ
(
X
a
b
)

1

2
X
a
b
ϵ
n
a
b
ξ
n
.
Note that projecting in this way may be construed as a loss of structure, insofar as
{

1
,
1
}
does not have the algebraic properties of rotations. But it is as good a way as any to represent an antisymmetric rank 2 tensor as an integer, which is what we need to do to adequately evaluate the model.
What, then, does the model predict for Alice and Bob’s measurements, recorded using these projection maps? For Alice, for any given choice of measurement vector
α
a
, the answer is given by,
P
α
(
A
a
b
(
α
a
,
λ
)
)

1

2
(
λ

2
ϵ
m
a
b
α
m
)
ϵ
n
a
b
α
n

λ
.
For Bob, meanwhile, for any choice of
β
a
, we find,
P
β
(
B
a
b
(
β
a
,
λ
)
)

1

2
(

λ

2
ϵ
m
a
b
β
m
)
ϵ
n
a
b
β
n


λ
.
By definition
λ

±
1
, so these results are correctly valued in the set
{

1
,
1
}
. Since we have assumed a uniform density function, it follows that
E
h
.
v
.
(
P
α
(
A
a
b
(
α
a
)
)

1
2

1
2

0
E
h
.
v
.
(
P
β
(
B
a
b
(
β
a
)
)


1
2
+
1
2

0
,
which means that Alice and Bob should be getting
+
1
and

1
about half the time each. This is in agreement with the quantum mechanical case.
But something is awry. Suppose that Alice and Bob pick their respective vectors
α
a
and
β
a
and then perform successive measurements with these measurement vectors, recording the results as
±
1
as they go. After many trials, Alice and Bob should have long lists of numbers. For Alice and Bob individually, if you took the average value of each of their results, you would find it tending to 0. This is what it means to say that the individual expectation values are zero. But now, what about the expectation value of the product of these? This value is supposed to be a prediction for the average of the product of Alice and Bob’s measurement results for each trial, recorded as integers. So, if Alice wrote down
+
1
for her first trial, and Bob wrote down
+
1
, the product of their outcomes for that trial would be
+
1
. If for the next trial, Alice wrote down
+
1
and Bob wrote down

1
, the product would be

1
. And so on. The quantum mechanical expectation value for the product of the measurement results,
E
q
.
m
.
(
A
B
)
, amounts to a prediction that, over the long run, the sequence of values of
±
1
calculated by multiplying Alice and Bob’s individual results for each trial will have an average value of

α
a
β
a
. This is the prediction that is confirmed by the experimental evidence, that violates the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt inequality, and that would have to be accounted for by a viable local, deterministic (generalized) hidden variable theory.
Does the model presented in section 3 accomplish this task? Decidedly not. Consider what happens on this model if Alice and Bob choose to record their results using
±
1
, via the projection maps defined above. One immediately sees that for any choices of
α
a
and
β
a
, if you take the product of Alice’s result and Bob’s result for a particular trial, you always get the same number. Specifically,
P
α
(
A
a
b
(
α
a
,
λ
)
)
P
β
(
B
a
b
(
β
a
,
λ
)
)


λ
2


1.
It follows that the relevant product expectation value, the expectation of the product of the results after projection, is,
E
h
.
v
.
(
P
α
(
A
a
b
(
α
a
)
)
P
β
(
B
a
b
(
β
a
)
)
)

1
2
(

1
+

1
)


1.
This is not consistent with the quantum mechanical case, nor with experiment. (It also fails to violate the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt inequality.)22
As I have already suggested, the problem stems from the product expectation value defined in Eq. (3.3). There we appeared to show that the product expectation value for Alice and Bob’s measurements was

α
a
β
a
, as expected from quantum mechanics. But we now see that we were comparing apples to oranges. The calculation in Eq. (3.3) is a formal trick, something that bears a passing resemblance to the expectation value we want to calculate, but which is actually irrelevant to the problem we were initially interested in. Eq. (3.3) does give some measure of the overlap between Alice and Bob’s results, but not the measure that we were trying to reproduce.
The considerations just given lead to a more general result. To state it, we begin by defining a new, broader notion of hidden variable model.23
Definition 4.1 A (local, deterministic) generalized hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment is an ordered sextuple
(
Λ
,
X
,
A
,
B
,
ρ
,
P
)
, where
Λ
is a space of complete states of the system,
X
is some set of possible states of the system and apparatus after measurement,
A
,
B
:
S
2
×
Λ

X
are maps from measurement vectors and complete state specifications to states of the system and apparatus after measurement for Alice and Bob respectively,
ρ
:
Λ

[
0
,
1
]
is a probability density function on the space of complete states, and
P

{
P
i
:
X

{

1
,
1
}
}
i

S
2
is a family of maps that provide a way to represent the elements of
X
as numbers
±
1
for each choice of measurement vector.24
As before, determinism is built into this definition insofar as
A
,
B
, and each member of
P
are required to be well-defined as functions, and locality is included in the requirement that
A
,
B
, and each member of
P
depend only on the measurement vector associated with the given measurement. The idea behind this last requirement is that a local generalized hidden variable model must be one on which not only are Alice’s measurement results independent of Bob’s measurement settings, but also the projection scheme by which Alice translates her
X

valued measurement results into integers
±
1
must be independent of Bob’s measurement settings (and vice versa).
The relevant expectation values can now be seen to be the expectation values of the observables
A
and
B
after they have been mapped to
{

1
,
1
}
. (We will use the symbol
E
g
.
h
.
v
to represent this new notion of expectation value.) We can thus stipulate more clearly that, in order for a generalized hidden variable model
(
Λ
,
X
,
A
,
B
,
ρ
,
P
)
to be satisfactory, it must be the case that for every choice of
a
and
b
, the following hold:25
E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
)


Λ
P
a
(
A
(
a
,
λ
)
)
ρ
(
λ
)
d
λ

0
(4.1)
E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
B
(
b
)
)


Λ
P
b
(
B
(
b
,
λ
)
)
ρ
(
λ
)
d
λ

0
(4.2)
E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b
)
)


Λ
P
a
(
A
(
a
,
λ
)
)
P
b
(
B
(
b
,
λ
)
)
ρ
(
λ
)
d
λ


a

b
(4.3)
In these new terms, the model presented above is indeed a local, deterministic generalized hidden variable model. But it does not reproduce the EPR-Bohm measurement results because it fails to satisfy Eq. (4.3).
These considerations suggest a simple no-go result that helps focus attention on the case of a generalized hidden variable model.26 As noted above, the following is an immediate corollary of Theorem 2.2.
Corollary 4.2 There does not exist a local, deterministic generalized hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment that reproduces the quantum mechanical expectation values.
Proof. Let
(
Λ
,
X
,
A
,
B
,
ρ
,
P
)
be a local, deterministic generalized hidden variable model. Define two new observables
A

,
B

:
S
2
×
Λ

{

1
,
1
}
as follows: for any
a
,
b

S
2
and any
λ

Λ
, set
A

(
a
,
λ
)

P
a
(
A
(
a
,
λ
)
)
and
B

(
b
,
λ
)

P
b
(
B
(
b
,
λ
)
)
. Now
(
Λ
,
A

,
B

,
ρ
)
is a hidden variable model (in the original sense of definition 2.1). Thus, for any
a
,
a

,
b
, and
b

, the expectation values of
A

and
B

must satisfy the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt inequality. It follows, by direct substitution, that
|
E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b
)
)

E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a
)
B
(
b

)
)
+
E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a

)
B
(
b
)
)
+
E
g
.
h
.
v
.
(
A
(
a

)
B
(
b

)
)
|

2.
(4.4)
As noted above, the quantum mechanical expectation values do not satisfy this inequality. Thus no local, deterministic generalized hidden variable model can reproduce the quantum mechanical expectation values for an EPR-Bohm experiment.

It follows that one cannot get around Bell-type theorems by considering more general representations of experimental outcomes.
5 FINAL REMARKS

The principal moral of this paper is that one cannot get around Bell-type arguments by generalizing the space of measurement outcomes, or equivalently, by representing the state of the particles after measurement with more sophisticated mathematical machinery. The reason for this is that ultimately the measurement data that exhibits the Bell-type-theorem-violating correlations consists of sequences of elements of the set
{

1
,
1
}
. It is these sequences, or at least their expectation values, that a (generalized) hidden variable model of the EPR-Bohm experiment needs to explain in order to be satisfactory. Corollary 4.2 shows how this is impossible, since the combination of any non-integer valued representation of measurement results with a map that identifies these with integers
±
1
simply recovers an observable in the standard sense of Bell-type theorems. And we already know that a hidden variable model with standard, integer-valued observables cannot successfully reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics.
This last point underscores the scope and generality of Bell-type theorems: they really do have the foundational importance typically attributed to them, contra the suggestion offered at the beginning of section 3 that Bell made a serious error in how he constrained the representation of EPR-Bohm measurement results. The model and the no-go result I present here may help to clarify how it is that Bell-type theorems apply even to models that look quite different from the models that appear to be the target of standard Bell-type theorems. But the present no-go result is at best a corollary of results that have been known for forty years.
Indeed, Bell understood very well that his argument was entirely independent of any concerns about what the mathematical and physical structure of the space of possible states
Λ
might turn out to be—concerns of just the sort that motivate the model described in this paper and other similar models discussed recently. As he put it,
…[Y]ou might still expect that it is a preoccupation with determinism that creates the problem. Note well then that the following argument makes no mention whatever of determinism. You might suspect that there is something specially peculiar about spin-1/2 particles. … So the following argument makes no reference to spin-1/2 particles, or any other particular particles. Finally you might suspect that the very notion of particle … has somehow led us astray. Indeed did not Einstein think that fields rather than particles are at the bottom of everything? So the following argument will not mention particles, nor indeed fields, nor any other particular picture of what goes on at the microscopic level. Nor will it involve any use of the words “quantum mechanical system”, which can have an unfortunate effect on the discussion. The difficulty is not created by any such picture or any such terminology. It is created by the prediction about the correlations in the visible outputs of certain conceivable experimental set-ups. (Bell, 1980, pg. 11)
As Bell says, what matters is precisely the correlations that in fact obtain in certain experiments—correlations between sequences of results recorded in the standard way. It is these correlations that we would want to explain with some successful model of the experiments. And, as Bell showed, it is precisely these correlations that cannot be explained with any local, deterministic hidden variable model.
As a coda to the present discussion, it is interesting to note that if one began with a different version of Bell’s theorem, in particular one of the probabilistic variety often associated with the Clauser-Horne inequality and with Jarrett’s analysis of Bell-type results, the same basic issues arise. In that setting one would have some joint distribution over what I call
A
and
B
above, which, in the “generalized” setting would be a probability measure on the space
X
×
X
. One could then claim to avoid Bell-type theorems by making the same sort of mistake made in Eq. (3.3)—namely taking the expectation value of the inner product (say) of the two elements of
X
associated with each point of
X
×
X
. As with the model discussed here, one could certainly give the appearance of violating Bell-type theorems in this way. But by the same considerations discussed in section 4, what one would really want would be the expectation value of the ordinary product after projection to
{

1
,
1
}
. And once again, we know this is impossible, precisely because of Bell-type theorems.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I am grateful to Shelly Goldstein, David Malament, John Manchak, Florin Moldoveanu, Abner Shimony, Howard Stein, and an anonymous referee for helpful comments on a previous draft of this paper. Thank you, too, to Jeff Barrett, Harvey Brown, David Malament, and Tim Maudlin for discussions on these and related topics and to David Hestenes for a helpful email exchange on Clifford algebras. I am especially grateful to Joy Christian for an informative correspondence and for his kind help on this project despite our continued disagreement. Finally, this paper has benefited from audiences at the Southern California Philosophy of Physics Group and the Maryland Foundations of Physics Group, and I am grateful to Christian Wüthrich and Jeff Bub for inviting me to make these presentation.
REFERENCES

Bell (1964) Bell, J. S. (1964). On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics, 1(3):195–200. Also published in Bell (1987).
Bell (1966) Bell, J. S. (1966). On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 38:447–452. Also published in Bell (1987).
Bell (1980) Bell, J. S. (1980). Bertlmann’s socks and the nature of reality. Ref.TH.2926-CERN. Also published in Bell (1987).
Bell (1987) Bell, J. S. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, New York.
Christian (2007a) Christian, J. (2007a). Disproof of Bell’s theorem by Clifford algebra valued local variables. arXiv:quant-ph/0703179.
Christian (2007b) Christian, J. (2007b). Disproof of Bell’s theorem: Further consolidations. arXiv:0707.1333 [quant-ph].
Christian (2007c) Christian, J. (2007c). Disproof of Bell’s theorem: Reply to critics. arXiv:quant-ph/0703244.
Christian (2008) Christian, J. (2008). Can Bell’s prescription for physical reality be considered complete? arXiv:0806.3078 [quant-ph].
Christian (2009) Christian, J. (2009). Disproofs of Bell, GHZ, and Hardy type theorems and the illusion of entanglement. arXiv:0904.4259 [quant-ph].
Christian (2010) Christian, J. (2010). Failure of Bell’s theorem and the local causality of the entangled photons. arXiv:1005.4932v2 [quant-ph].
Christian (2011a) Christian, J. (2011a). Disproof of Bell’s theorem. arXiv:1103.1879v1 [quant-ph].
Christian (2011b) Christian, J. (2011b). What really sets the upper bound on quantum correlations? arXiv:1101.1958v1 [quant-ph].
Christian (2012) Christian, J. (2012). Disproof of Bell’s Theorem: Illuminating the Illusion of Entanglement. BrownWalker Press, Boca Raton, FL.
Christian (2013) Christian, J. (2013). Whither all the scope and generality of Bell’s theorem? arXiv:2013.1653 [physics.gen-ph].
Clauser and Horne (1974) Clauser, J. F. and Horne, M. A. (1974). Experimental consequences of objective local theories. Physical Review D, 10(2):526–535.
Clauser et al. (1969) Clauser, J. F., Horne, M. A., Shimony, A., and Holt, R. A. (1969). Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories. Physical Review Letters, 23(15):880–884.
Grangier (2007) Grangier, P. (2007). “disproof of Bell’s theorem”: more critics. arXiv:07072223 [quant-ph].
Jarrett (1984) Jarrett, J. P. (1984). On the physical significance of the locality conditions in the Bell arguments. Noûs, 18(4):569–589.
Jarrett (1989) Jarrett, J. P. (1989). Bell’s theorem: A guide to the implications. In Cushing, J. T. and McMullin, E., editors, Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN.
Malament (2006) Malament, D. B. (2006). Notes on Bell’s theorem. Available at lps.uci.edu/malament/prob-de … esBell.pdf.
Malament (2012) Malament, D. B. (2012). Topics in the Foundations of General Relativity and Newtonian Gravitation Theory. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Moldoveanu (2011) Moldoveanu, F. (2011). Disproof of Joy Christian’s “Disproof of Bell’s theorem”. arXiv:1109.0535 [quant-ph].
Penrose and Rindler (1987) Penrose, R. and Rindler, W. (1987). Spinors and Space-Time (2 Volumes). Cambridge University Press, New York.
Pitowsky (1989) Pitowsky, I. (1989). Quantum Probability—Quantum Logic. Springer-Verlag, New York.
Shimony (2009) Shimony, A. (2009). Bell’s theorem. In Zalta, E. N., editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition). Available at plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2 … l-theorem/.
Want to hear about new tools we’re making? Sign up to our mailing list for occasional updates.

Subscribe

If you find a rendering bug, file an issue on GitHub. Or, have a go at fixing it yourself – the renderer is open source!”

For everything else, email us at feedback@arxiv-vanity.com.

A project from Replicate, with help from LaTeXML. Contribute on GitHub. Latest papers.

The basic idea is that it may not be a good idea to break up an informatively functional series of bubbly groups, for whatever examplification of , or externalization between flow parts, because that would or could fragment the spatial-temporal ‘urge’ to unify a formal and a contextual urge, where the source and the resourcing of variable connections may be lost thereby.

Ideas need no closure at a point of imminence, for a re-view will tend to justify and disintegrate such parts of derivatively tenuous point, that appear to vary the intervals defining both the pull back and the brought foreward ‘magnetic forces’ operating within particular fields’ variation.

This is basic, and yes these types of long standing or newly arisen movements, can not only develop into the program referred as with, recently, between the old classifications which matter: solid, liquid, gas, and plasma, but further , much further, the elements comprising their movements from the simulated effect that is, ‘artificially created’

The idea that the vanity of existence has a subordinately developed inception in a chaotic genome of some kind analogous to the organic pool of genetically maximally overebundant redundancy, that progressively clumps in bubbles of hypothetical duplex structural mirroring, does create the illusion of looking into a mirror with fear and trembling , has the blessed imprimatur of higher grounded beneficience as comforting peace must do.

But this point, remains conclusively inconclusive, yet inconclusive in it’s conclusion for at least another generation, to form a new formal design ( model), and that’s the point of the start of ever improved nearer to perfected simulations , which finally remove the moralistic restraints from what may be considered as irrelevantly unreasonable.